Philosophy Faculty Database
Philosophy
Arts & Sciences
Duke University

 HOME > Arts & Sciences > Philosophy > Faculty    Search Help Login pdf version printable version 

Publications of Felipe De Brigard    :chronological  alphabetical  by type listing:

%%    
@article{fds376061,
   Author = {Niemi, L and Washington, N and Workman, C and Arcila-Valenzuela, M and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {The emotional impact of baseless discrediting of knowledge:
             An empirical investigation of epistemic injustice.},
   Journal = {Acta psychologica},
   Volume = {244},
   Pages = {104157},
   Year = {2024},
   Month = {April},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.actpsy.2024.104157},
   Abstract = {According to theoretical work on epistemic injustice,
             baseless discrediting of the knowledge of people with
             marginalized social identities is a central driver of
             prejudice and discrimination. Discrediting of knowledge may
             sometimes be subtle, but it is pernicious, inducing chronic
             stress and coping strategies such as emotional avoidance. In
             this research, we sought to deepen the understanding of
             epistemic injustice's impact by examining emotional
             responses to being discredited and assessing if marginalized
             social group membership predicts these responses. We
             conducted a novel series of three experiments (Total
             N = 1690) in which participants (1) shared their factual
             knowledge about how a game worked or their personal feelings
             about the game; (2) received discrediting feedback
             (invalidating remarks), validating feedback (affirming
             remarks), or insulting feedback (general negative social
             evaluation); and then (3) reported their affect. In all
             three studies, on average, affective responses to
             discrediting feedback were less negative than to insulting
             feedback, and more negative than to validating feedback.
             Participants who shared their knowledge reported more
             negative affect after discrediting feedback than
             participants who shared their feelings. There were
             consistent individual differences, including a
             twice-replicated finding of reduced negative affect after
             receiving discrediting and insulting feedback for Black men
             compared to White men and women and Black women. Black men's
             race-based traumatic symptom scores predicted their
             affective responses to discrediting and insulting feedback,
             suggesting that experience with discrimination contributed
             to the emotional processing of a key aspect of epistemic
             injustice: remarks conveying baseless discrediting of
             knowledge.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.actpsy.2024.104157},
   Key = {fds376061}
}

@article{fds376898,
   Author = {Krasich, K and O'Neill, K and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Looking at Mental Images: Eye-Tracking Mental Simulation
             During Retrospective Causal Judgment.},
   Journal = {Cognitive science},
   Volume = {48},
   Number = {3},
   Pages = {e13426},
   Year = {2024},
   Month = {March},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/cogs.13426},
   Abstract = {How do people evaluate causal relationships? Do they just
             consider what actually happened, or do they also consider
             what could have counterfactually happened? Using eye
             tracking and Gaussian process modeling, we investigated how
             people mentally simulated past events to judge what caused
             the outcomes to occur. Participants played a virtual
             ball-shooting game and then-while looking at a blank
             screen-mentally simulated (a) what actually happened, (b)
             what counterfactually could have happened, or (c) what
             caused the outcome to happen. Our findings showed that
             participants moved their eyes in patterns consistent with
             the actual or counterfactual events that they mentally
             simulated. When simulating what caused the outcome to occur,
             participants moved their eyes consistent with simulations of
             counterfactual possibilities. These results favor
             counterfactual theories of causal reasoning, demonstrate how
             eye movements can reflect simulation during this reasoning
             and provide a novel approach for investigating retrospective
             causal reasoning and counterfactual thinking.},
   Doi = {10.1111/cogs.13426},
   Key = {fds376898}
}

@article{fds373975,
   Author = {Krasich, K and O'Neill, K and Murray, S and Brockmole, JR and De
             Brigard, F and Nuthmann, A},
   Title = {A computational modeling approach to investigating mind
             wandering-related adjustments to gaze behavior during scene
             viewing.},
   Journal = {Cognition},
   Volume = {242},
   Pages = {105624},
   Year = {2024},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2023.105624},
   Abstract = {Research on gaze control has long shown that increased
             visual-cognitive processing demands in scene viewing are
             associated with longer fixation durations. More recently,
             though, longer durations have also been linked to mind
             wandering, a perceptually decoupled state of attention
             marked by decreased visual-cognitive processing. Toward
             better understanding the relationship between fixation
             durations and visual-cognitive processing, we ran
             simulations using an established random-walk model for
             saccade timing and programming and assessed which model
             parameters best predicted modulations in fixation durations
             associated with mind wandering compared to attentive
             viewing. Mind wandering-related fixation durations were best
             described as an increase in the variability of the
             fixation-generating process, leading to more
             variable-sometimes very long-durations. In contrast, past
             research showed that increased processing demands increased
             the mean duration of the fixation-generating process. The
             findings thus illustrate that mind wandering and processing
             demands modulate fixation durations through different
             mechanisms in scene viewing. This suggests that processing
             demands cannot be inferred from changes in fixation
             durations without understanding the underlying mechanism by
             which these changes were generated.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.cognition.2023.105624},
   Key = {fds373975}
}

@article{fds373542,
   Author = {Miceli, K and Morales-Torres, R and Khoudary, A and Faul, L and Parikh,
             N and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Perceived plausibility modulates hippocampal activity in
             episodic counterfactual thinking.},
   Journal = {Hippocampus},
   Volume = {34},
   Number = {1},
   Pages = {2-6},
   Year = {2024},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/hipo.23583},
   Abstract = {Episodic counterfactual thinking (ECT) consists of imagining
             alternative outcomes to past personal events. Previous
             research has shown that ECT shares common neural substrates
             with episodic future thinking (EFT): our ability to imagine
             possible future events. Both ECT and EFT have been shown to
             critically depend on the hippocampus, and past research has
             explored hippocampal engagement as a function of the
             perceived plausibility of an imagined future event. However,
             the extent to which the hippocampus is modulated by
             perceived plausibility during ECT is unknown. In this study,
             we combine two functional magnetic resonance imaging
             datasets to investigate whether perceived plausibility
             modulates hippocampal activity during ECT. Our results
             indicate that plausibility parametrically modulates
             hippocampal activity during ECT, and that such modulation is
             confined to the left anterior portion of the hippocampus.
             Moreover, our results indicate that this modulation is
             positive, such that increased activity in the left anterior
             hippocampus is associated with higher ratings of ECT
             plausibility. We suggest that neither effort nor difficulty
             alone can account for these results, and instead suggest
             possible alternatives to explain the role of the hippocampus
             during the construction of plausible and implausible
             ECT.},
   Doi = {10.1002/hipo.23583},
   Key = {fds373542}
}

@article{fds374206,
   Author = {Morales-Torres, R and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {On the frequency and nature of the cues that elicit déjà
             vu and involuntary autobiographical memories.},
   Journal = {The Behavioral and brain sciences},
   Volume = {46},
   Pages = {e370},
   Year = {2023},
   Month = {November},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0140525x23000134},
   Abstract = {Barzykowski and Moulin suggest that déjà vu and
             involuntary autobiographical memories recruit similar
             retrieval processes. Here, we invite the authors to clarify
             three issues: (1) What mechanism prevents déjà vu to
             happen more frequently? (2) What is the role of semantic
             cues in involuntary autobiographical retrieval? and (3) How
             déjà vu relates to non-believed memories?},
   Doi = {10.1017/s0140525x23000134},
   Key = {fds374206}
}

@article{fds369853,
   Author = {Murray, S and Bermúdez, JP and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Moralization and self-control strategy selection.},
   Journal = {Psychonomic bulletin & review},
   Volume = {30},
   Number = {4},
   Pages = {1586-1595},
   Year = {2023},
   Month = {August},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.3758/s13423-023-02257-7},
   Abstract = {To manage conflicts between temptation and commitment,
             people use self-control. The process model of self-control
             outlines different strategies for managing the onset and
             experience of temptation. However, little is known about the
             decision-making factors underlying strategy selection.
             Across three experiments (N = 317), we tested whether the
             moral valence of a commitment predicts how people advise
             attentional self-control strategies. In Experiments 1 and 2,
             people rated attentional focus strategies as significantly
             more effective for people tempted to break moral relative to
             immoral commitments, even when controlling for perceived
             temptation and trait self-control. Experiment 3 showed that
             as people perceived commitments to have more positive moral
             valence, they judged attentional focus strategies to be
             significantly more effective relative to attentional
             distraction strategies. Moreover, this effect was partly
             mediated by perceived differences in motivation. These
             results indicate that moralization informs decision-making
             processes related to self-control strategy
             selection.},
   Doi = {10.3758/s13423-023-02257-7},
   Key = {fds369853}
}

@article{fds371448,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {"Repressed Memory" Makes No Sense.},
   Journal = {Topics in cognitive science},
   Year = {2023},
   Month = {June},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/tops.12677},
   Abstract = {The expression "repressed memory" was introduced over 100
             years ago as a theoretical term purportedly referring to an
             unobservable psychological entity postulated by Freud's
             seduction theory. That theory, however, and its hypothesized
             cognitive architecture, have been thoroughly debunked-yet
             the term "repressed memory" seems to remain. In this paper,
             I offer a philosophical evaluation of the meaning of this
             theoretical term as well as an argument to question its
             scientific status by comparing it to other cases of
             theoretical terms that have either survived scientific
             change-such as "atom" or "gene"-or that have perished, such
             as "black bile." Ultimately, I argue that "repressed memory"
             is more like "black bile" than "atom" or "gene" and, thus,
             recommend its demotion from our scientific
             vocabulary.},
   Doi = {10.1111/tops.12677},
   Key = {fds371448}
}

@article{fds369341,
   Author = {Boone, T and Van Rooy and N and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Not Every Thing Must Go.},
   Journal = {Journal of cognitive neuroscience},
   Volume = {35},
   Number = {3},
   Pages = {376-379},
   Year = {2023},
   Month = {March},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1162/jocn_a_01931},
   Abstract = {In The Entangled Brain, Pessoa criticizes standard
             approaches in cognitive neuroscience in which the brain is
             seen as a functionally decomposable, modular system with
             causal operations built up hierarchically. Instead, he
             advocates for an emergentist perspective whereby dynamic
             brain networks are associated, not with traditional
             psychological categories, but with behavioral functions
             characterized in evolutionary terms. Here, we raise a number
             of concerns with such a radical approach. We ultimately
             believe that although much revision to cognitive
             neuroscience is welcome and needed, Pessoa's more radical
             proposals may be counterproductive.},
   Doi = {10.1162/jocn_a_01931},
   Key = {fds369341}
}

@article{fds365621,
   Author = {Murray, S and Krasich, K and Irving, Z and Nadelhoffer, T and De
             Brigard, F},
   Title = {Mental control and attributions of blame for negligent
             wrongdoing.},
   Journal = {Journal of experimental psychology. General},
   Volume = {152},
   Number = {1},
   Pages = {120-138},
   Year = {2023},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/xge0001262},
   Abstract = {Third-personal judgments of blame are typically sensitive to
             what an agent knows and desires. However, when people act
             negligently, they do not know what they are doing and do not
             desire the outcomes of their negligence. How, then, do
             people attribute blame for negligent wrongdoing? We propose
             that people attribute blame for negligent wrongdoing based
             on perceived <i>mental</i> <i>control</i>, or the degree to
             which an agent guides their thoughts and attention over
             time. To acquire information about others' mental control,
             people self-project their own perceived mental control to
             anchor third-personal judgments about mental control and
             concomitant responsibility for negligent wrongdoing. In four
             experiments (<i>N</i> = 841), we tested whether perceptions
             of mental control drive third-personal judgments of blame
             for negligent wrongdoing. Study 1 showed that the ease with
             which people can counterfactually imagine an individual
             being non-negligent mediated the relationship between
             judgments of control and blame. Studies 2a and 2b indicated
             that perceived mental control has a strong effect on
             judgments of blame for negligent wrongdoing and that
             first-personal judgments of mental control are moderately
             correlated with third-personal judgments of blame for
             negligent wrongdoing. Finally, we used an autobiographical
             memory manipulation in Study 3 to make personal episodes of
             forgetfulness salient. Participants for whom past personal
             episodes of forgetfulness were made salient judged negligent
             wrongdoers less harshly compared with a control group for
             whom past episodes of negligence were not salient.
             Collectively, these findings suggest that first-personal
             judgments of mental control drive third-personal judgments
             of blame for negligent wrongdoing and indicate a novel role
             for counterfactual thinking in the attribution of
             responsibility. (PsycInfo Database Record (c) 2023 APA, all
             rights reserved).},
   Doi = {10.1037/xge0001262},
   Key = {fds365621}
}

@article{fds372917,
   Author = {Uddin, LQ and Betzel, RF and Cohen, JR and Damoiseaux, JS and De
             Brigard, F and Eickhoff, SB and Fornito, A and Gratton, C and Gordon,
             EM and Laird, AR and Larson-Prior, L and McIntosh, AR and Nickerson, LD and Pessoa, L and Pinho, AL and Poldrack, RA and Razi, A and Sadaghiani, S and Shine, JM and Yendiki, A and Yeo, BTT and Spreng,
             RN},
   Title = {Controversies and progress on standardization of large-scale
             brain network nomenclature.},
   Journal = {Network neuroscience (Cambridge, Mass.)},
   Volume = {7},
   Number = {3},
   Pages = {864-905},
   Publisher = {M I T PRESS},
   Year = {2023},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1162/netn_a_00323},
   Abstract = {Progress in scientific disciplines is accompanied by
             standardization of terminology. Network neuroscience, at the
             level of macroscale organization of the brain, is beginning
             to confront the challenges associated with developing a
             taxonomy of its fundamental explanatory constructs. The
             Workgroup for HArmonized Taxonomy of NETworks (WHATNET) was
             formed in 2020 as an Organization for Human Brain Mapping
             (OHBM)-endorsed best practices committee to provide
             recommendations on points of consensus, identify open
             questions, and highlight areas of ongoing debate in the
             service of moving the field toward standardized reporting of
             network neuroscience results. The committee conducted a
             survey to catalog current practices in large-scale brain
             network nomenclature. A few well-known network names (e.g.,
             default mode network) dominated responses to the survey, and
             a number of illuminating points of disagreement emerged. We
             summarize survey results and provide initial considerations
             and recommendations from the workgroup. This perspective
             piece includes a selective review of challenges to this
             enterprise, including (1) network scale, resolution, and
             hierarchies; (2) interindividual variability of networks;
             (3) dynamics and nonstationarity of networks; (4)
             consideration of network affiliations of subcortical
             structures; and (5) consideration of multimodal information.
             We close with minimal reporting guidelines for the cognitive
             and network neuroscience communities to adopt.},
   Doi = {10.1162/netn_a_00323},
   Key = {fds372917}
}

@article{fds368517,
   Author = {Krasich, K and Simmons, C and O'Neill, K and Giattino, CM and De
             Brigard, F and Sinnott-Armstrong, W and Mudrik, L and Woldorff,
             MG},
   Title = {Prestimulus oscillatory brain activity interacts with evoked
             recurrent processing to facilitate conscious visual
             perception.},
   Journal = {Sci Rep},
   Volume = {12},
   Number = {1},
   Pages = {22126},
   Year = {2022},
   Month = {December},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/s41598-022-25720-2},
   Abstract = {We investigated whether prestimulus alpha-band oscillatory
             activity and stimulus-elicited recurrent processing interact
             to facilitate conscious visual perception. Participants
             tried to perceive a visual stimulus that was perceptually
             masked through object substitution masking (OSM). We showed
             that attenuated prestimulus alpha power was associated with
             greater negative-polarity stimulus-evoked ERP activity that
             resembled the visual awareness negativity (VAN), previously
             argued to reflect recurrent processing related to conscious
             perception. This effect, however, was not associated with
             better perception. Instead, when prestimulus alpha power was
             elevated, a preferred prestimulus alpha phase was associated
             with a greater VAN-like negativity, which was then
             associated with better cue perception. Cue perception was
             worse when prestimulus alpha power was elevated but the
             stimulus occurred at a nonoptimal prestimulus alpha phase
             and the VAN-like negativity was low. Our findings suggest
             that prestimulus alpha activity at a specific phase enables
             temporally selective recurrent processing that facilitates
             conscious perception in OSM.},
   Doi = {10.1038/s41598-022-25720-2},
   Key = {fds368517}
}

@article{fds363449,
   Author = {Setton, R and Mwilambwe-Tshilobo, L and Girn, M and Lockrow, AW and Baracchini, G and Hughes, C and Lowe, AJ and Cassidy, BN and Li, J and Luh,
             W-M and Bzdok, D and Leahy, RM and Ge, T and Margulies, DS and Misic, B and Bernhardt, BC and Stevens, WD and De Brigard and F and Kundu, P and Turner,
             GR and Spreng, RN},
   Title = {Age differences in the functional architecture of the human
             brain.},
   Journal = {Cerebral cortex (New York, N.Y. : 1991)},
   Volume = {33},
   Number = {1},
   Pages = {114-134},
   Year = {2022},
   Month = {December},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/cercor/bhac056},
   Abstract = {The intrinsic functional organization of the brain changes
             into older adulthood. Age differences are observed at
             multiple spatial scales, from global reductions in
             modularity and segregation of distributed brain systems, to
             network-specific patterns of dedifferentiation. Whether
             dedifferentiation reflects an inevitable, global shift in
             brain function with age, circumscribed, experience-dependent
             changes, or both, is uncertain. We employed a multimethod
             strategy to interrogate dedifferentiation at multiple
             spatial scales. Multi-echo (ME) resting-state fMRI was
             collected in younger (n = 181) and older (n = 120)
             healthy adults. Cortical parcellation sensitive to
             individual variation was implemented for precision
             functional mapping of each participant while preserving
             group-level parcel and network labels. ME-fMRI processing
             and gradient mapping identified global and macroscale
             network differences. Multivariate functional connectivity
             methods tested for microscale, edge-level differences. Older
             adults had lower BOLD signal dimensionality, consistent with
             global network dedifferentiation. Gradients were largely
             age-invariant. Edge-level analyses revealed discrete,
             network-specific dedifferentiation patterns in older adults.
             Visual and somatosensory regions were more integrated within
             the functional connectome; default and frontoparietal
             control network regions showed greater connectivity; and the
             dorsal attention network was more integrated with
             heteromodal regions. These findings highlight the importance
             of multiscale, multimethod approaches to characterize the
             architecture of functional brain aging.},
   Doi = {10.1093/cercor/bhac056},
   Key = {fds363449}
}

@article{fds367649,
   Author = {Khoudary, A and O'Neill, K and Faul, L and Murray, S and Smallman, R and De
             Brigard, F},
   Title = {Neural differences between internal and external episodic
             counterfactual thoughts.},
   Journal = {Philosophical transactions of the Royal Society of London.
             Series B, Biological sciences},
   Volume = {377},
   Number = {1866},
   Pages = {20210337},
   Year = {2022},
   Month = {December},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2021.0337},
   Abstract = {Episodic counterfactual thoughts (eCFT) consist of imagining
             alternative outcomes to past experiences. A common sub-class
             of eCFT-<i>upward</i> eCFT-involves imagining how past
             negative experiences could have been <i>better</i>, either
             because one could have done something differently (internal)
             or because something about the circumstances could have been
             different (external). Although previous neuroimaging
             research has shown that the brain's default mode network
             (DMN) supports upward eCFT, it is unclear how it is
             differentially recruited during internal versus external
             upward eCFT. We collected functional magnetic resonance
             imaging data while participants remembered negative
             autobiographical memories, generated either internal or
             external upward eCFT for the memory, and then rated the
             plausibility, perceived control and difficulty of eCFT
             generation. Both internal and external eCFT engaged midline
             regions of cingulate cortex, a central node of the DMN. Most
             activity differentiating eCFT, however, occurred outside the
             DMN. External eCFT engaged cuneus, angular gyrus and
             precuneus, whereas internal eCFT engaged posterior cingulate
             and precentral gyrus. Angular gyrus and precuneus were
             additionally sensitive to perceived plausibility of external
             eCFT, while postcentral gyrus and insula activity scaled
             with perceived plausibility of internal eCFT. These results
             highlight the key brain regions that might be involved in
             cases of maladaptive mental simulations. This article is
             part of the theme issue 'Thinking about possibilities:
             mechanisms, ontogeny, functions and phylogeny'.},
   Doi = {10.1098/rstb.2021.0337},
   Key = {fds367649}
}

@article{fds368059,
   Author = {Khoudary, A and Hanna, E and O'Neill, K and Iyengar, V and Clifford, S and Cabeza, R and De Brigard and F and Sinnott-Armstrong,
             W},
   Title = {A functional neuroimaging investigation of Moral Foundations
             Theory.},
   Journal = {Social neuroscience},
   Volume = {17},
   Number = {6},
   Pages = {491-507},
   Year = {2022},
   Month = {December},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17470919.2022.2148737},
   Abstract = {Moral Foundations Theory (MFT) posits that the human mind
             contains modules (or "foundations") that are functionally
             specialized to moralize unique dimensions of the social
             world: Authority, Loyalty, Purity, Harm, Fairness, and
             Liberty. Despite this strong claim about cognitive
             architecture, it is unclear whether neural activity during
             moral reasoning exhibits this modular structure. Here, we
             use spatiotemporal partial least squares correlation (PLSC)
             analyses of fMRI data collected during judgments of
             foundation-specific violations to investigate whether MFT's
             cognitive modularity claim extends to the neural level. A
             mean-centered PLSC analysis returned two latent variables
             that differentiated between social norm and moral foundation
             violations, functionally segregated Purity, Loyalty,
             Physical Harm, and Fairness from the other foundations, and
             suggested that Authority has a different neural basis than
             other binding foundations. Non-rotated PLSC analyses
             confirmed that neural activity distinguished social norm
             from moral foundation violations, and distinguished
             individualizing and binding moral foundations if Authority
             is dropped from the binding foundations. Purity violations
             were persistently associated with amygdala activity, whereas
             moral foundation violations more broadly tended to engage
             the default network. Our results constitute partial evidence
             for neural modularity and motivate further research on the
             novel groupings identified by the PLSC analyses.},
   Doi = {10.1080/17470919.2022.2148737},
   Key = {fds368059}
}

@article{fds363780,
   Author = {Faul, L and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {The moderating effects of nostalgia on mood and optimism
             during the COVID-19 pandemic.},
   Journal = {Memory (Hove, England)},
   Volume = {30},
   Number = {9},
   Pages = {1103-1117},
   Year = {2022},
   Month = {October},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09658211.2022.2082481},
   Abstract = {The initial waves of the coronavirus pandemic amplified
             feelings of depression, psychological fatigue and pessimism
             for the future. Past research suggests that nostalgia helps
             to repair negative moods by boosting current and
             future-oriented positive affect, thereby strengthening
             psychological resilience. Accordingly, the present study
             investigated whether nostalgia moderated the relationship
             between pandemic experience and individual differences in
             mood and optimism. Across two studies we assessed
             psychosocial self-report data from a total of 293 online
             participants (22-72 years old; mean age 38; 109 females, 184
             males) during the first two waves of the pandemic.
             Participants completed comprehensive questionnaires that
             probed state and trait characteristics related to mood and
             memory, such as the Profile of Mood States, Nostalgia
             Inventory and State Optimism Measure. Our findings indicate
             that during the initial wave of coronavirus cases, higher
             levels of nostalgia buffered against deteriorating mood
             states associated with concern over the pandemic. Nostalgia
             also boosted optimism for participants experiencing negative
             mood, and optimism predicted subjective mood improvement one
             week later. This shielding effect of nostalgia on optimism
             was replicated during the second wave of coronavirus cases.
             The present findings support the role of nostalgia in
             promoting emotional homeostasis and resilience during
             periods of psychological distress.},
   Doi = {10.1080/09658211.2022.2082481},
   Key = {fds363780}
}

@article{fds362040,
   Author = {O'Neill, K and Henne, P and Bello, P and Pearson, J and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Confidence and gradation in causal judgment.},
   Journal = {Cognition},
   Volume = {223},
   Pages = {105036},
   Year = {2022},
   Month = {June},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2022.105036},
   Abstract = {When comparing the roles of the lightning strike and the dry
             climate in causing the forest fire, one might think that the
             lightning strike is more of a cause than the dry climate, or
             one might think that the lightning strike completely caused
             the fire while the dry conditions did not cause it at all.
             Psychologists and philosophers have long debated whether
             such causal judgments are graded; that is, whether people
             treat some causes as stronger than others. To address this
             debate, we first reanalyzed data from four recent studies.
             We found that causal judgments were actually multimodal:
             although most causal judgments made on a continuous scale
             were categorical, there was also some gradation. We then
             tested two competing explanations for this gradation: the
             confidence explanation, which states that people make graded
             causal judgments because they have varying degrees of belief
             in causal relations, and the strength explanation, which
             states that people make graded causal judgments because they
             believe that causation itself is graded. Experiment 1 tested
             the confidence explanation and showed that gradation in
             causal judgments was indeed moderated by confidence: people
             tended to make graded causal judgments when they were
             unconfident, but they tended to make more categorical causal
             judgments when they were confident. Experiment 2 tested the
             causal strength explanation and showed that although
             confidence still explained variation in causal judgments, it
             did not explain away the effects of normality, causal
             structure, or the number of candidate causes. Overall, we
             found that causal judgments were multimodal and that people
             make graded judgments both when they think a cause is weak
             and when they are uncertain about its causal
             role.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.cognition.2022.105036},
   Key = {fds362040}
}

@article{fds358346,
   Author = {O'Neill, K and Liu, A and Yin, S and Brady, T and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Effects of category learning strategies on recognition
             memory.},
   Journal = {Memory & cognition},
   Volume = {50},
   Number = {3},
   Pages = {512-526},
   Year = {2022},
   Month = {April},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.3758/s13421-021-01207-9},
   Abstract = {Extant research has shown that previously acquired
             categorical knowledge affects recognition memory, and that
             differences in category learning strategies impact
             classification accuracy. However, it is unknown whether
             different learning strategies also have downstream effects
             on subsequent recognition memory. The present study
             investigates the effect of two unidimensional rule-based
             category learning strategies - learning (a) with or without
             explicit instruction, and (b) with or without supervision -
             on subsequent recognition memory. Our findings suggest that
             acquiring categorical knowledge increased both hits
             (Experiments 1 and 2) and false-alarms (Experiment 1) for
             category-congruent items regardless of the particular
             strategy employed in initially learning these categories.
             There were, however, small processing speed advantages
             during recognition memory for both explicit instruction and
             supervised practice relative to neither (Experiment 2). We
             discuss these findings in the context of how prior knowledge
             influences recognition memory, and in relation to similar
             findings showing schematic effects on episodic
             memory.},
   Doi = {10.3758/s13421-021-01207-9},
   Key = {fds358346}
}

@article{fds362477,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Umanath, S and Irish, M},
   Title = {Rethinking the distinction between episodic and semantic
             memory: Insights from the past, present, and
             future.},
   Journal = {Memory & cognition},
   Volume = {50},
   Number = {3},
   Pages = {459-463},
   Year = {2022},
   Month = {April},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.3758/s13421-022-01299-x},
   Abstract = {On the 50th anniversary of Tulving's introduction of the
             celebrated distinction between episodic and semantic memory,
             it seems more than fitting to revisit his proposal in light
             of recent conceptual and methodological advances in the
             field. This Special Issue of Memory & Cognition brings
             together researchers doing cutting-edge work at the
             intersection between episodic and semantic memory to
             showcase studies directly probing this psychological
             distinction, as well as articles that seek to provide
             conceptual and theoretical accounts to understand their
             interaction. The 14 articles presented here highlight the
             need to critically examine the way in which we conceptualize
             not only the relationship between episodic and semantic
             memory, but also the interplay between declarative and
             non-declarative memory, and the myriad implications of such
             conceptual changes. In many ways, we suggest this Special
             Issue might serve as a call to action for our field,
             inspiring future work to challenge pre-existing conceptions
             and stimulate new directions in this fast-moving
             field.},
   Doi = {10.3758/s13421-022-01299-x},
   Key = {fds362477}
}

@article{fds372918,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = { Perceptual Imagination and Perceptual Memory
              Edited by Fiona Macpherson and Fabian
             Dorsch},
   Journal = {Analysis},
   Volume = {81},
   Number = {4},
   Pages = {827-831},
   Publisher = {Oxford University Press (OUP)},
   Year = {2022},
   Month = {February},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/analys/anab001},
   Doi = {10.1093/analys/anab001},
   Key = {fds372918}
}

@article{fds358756,
   Author = {Lipkus, IM and Mays, D and Sheeran, P and Pan, W and Cameron, LD and De
             Brigard, F},
   Title = {Effects of mental simulation of future waterpipe tobacco
             smoking on attitudes, perceived harms and intended use among
             young adults.},
   Journal = {Journal of behavioral medicine},
   Volume = {45},
   Number = {1},
   Pages = {76-89},
   Year = {2022},
   Month = {February},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10865-021-00245-7},
   Abstract = {The desire to engage in waterpipe tobacco smoking (WTS) may
             occur when smokers and nonsmokers conjure positive mental
             simulations of WTS. However, effects of these simulations on
             desire to smoke waterpipe tobacco and potential mediators
             are unexplored. This research addressed these effects among
             young adult waterpipe tobacco smokers and nonsmokers. Two
             online studies were conducted with adults ages 18-30. In
             Study 1, 200 smokers, 190 susceptible nonsmokers, and 182
             nonsusceptible nonsmokers were randomized to mentally
             simulate or not WTS in the future. In Study 2, 234 smokers
             and 241 susceptible nonsmokers were randomized to four arms:
             no simulation or simulations that varied valence of
             experience (positive, negative or no valence provided). Main
             outcomes were immediate desire to smoke waterpipe tobacco,
             cognitive and affective attitudes, and perceived harms. In
             Study 1, mental simulations increased the desire to smoke
             waterpipe tobacco among smokers. In Study 2, asking
             participants to simulate WTS positively or with no valence
             instruction increased desire to smoke relative to negative
             valence instruction or no simulation. Negative simulations
             reduced perceived probability of smoking within a month
             compared to positive simulations. Effects on desire to
             engage in WTS were mediated by cognitive and affective
             attitudes among susceptible nonsmokers and by cognitive
             attitudes among smokers. These findings suggest that
             exploring when and how often mental simulations about WTS
             are evoked and their potency for promoting prevention and
             cessation of WTS merit further attention.},
   Doi = {10.1007/s10865-021-00245-7},
   Key = {fds358756}
}

@article{fds367259,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Robins, S},
   Title = {Memory},
   Pages = {325-343},
   Booktitle = {Mind, Cognition, and Neuroscience: A Philosophical
             Introduction},
   Year = {2022},
   Month = {January},
   ISBN = {9781138392342},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9781003241898-24},
   Abstract = {The idea that there are different kinds of memory is old.
             Aristotle, for instance, famously distinguished between
             memory and reminiscence, the former roughly corresponding to
             the retention of temporally based information from past
             events, and the latter to the act of retrieving previously
             stored information. Cognitive psychologists and
             neuroscientists also agree that remembering is a diachronic
             process, but they tend to think that it involves three
             stages: encoding, storage, and retrieval. Declarative or
             explicit memory is often divided into two subclasses as
             well, thanks to Tulving's influential distinction between
             episodic memory and semantic memory. The shifting of
             memories from one system to another is thought to aid in
             overall memory storage by preventing the hippocampus from
             becoming too overloaded with memories. The precise timescale
             for systems consolidation is a matter of some debate; it is
             thought to occur anywhere from a few weeks or months to
             possibly even years or decades after the initial
             encoding.},
   Doi = {10.4324/9781003241898-24},
   Key = {fds367259}
}

@article{fds369061,
   Author = {O'Neill, K and Henne, P and Pearson, J and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Measuring and Modeling Confidence in Human Causal
             Judgment},
   Journal = {Proceedings of the 44th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive
             Science Society: Cognitive Diversity, CogSci
             2022},
   Pages = {446-452},
   Year = {2022},
   Month = {January},
   Abstract = {The human capacity for causal judgment has long been thought
             to depend on an ability to consider counterfactual
             alternatives: the lightning strike caused the forest fire
             because had it not struck, the forest fire would not have
             ensued. To accommodate psychological effects on causal
             judgment, a range of recent accounts of causal judgment have
             proposed that people probabilistically sample counterfactual
             alternatives from which they compute a graded index of
             causal strength. While such models have had success in
             describing the influence of probability on causal judgments,
             among other effects, we show that these models make further
             untested predictions: probability should also influence
             people's metacognitive confidence in their causal judgments.
             In a large (N=3020) sample of participants in a causal
             judgment task, we found evidence that normality indeed
             influences people's confidence in their causal judgments and
             that these influences were predicted by a counterfactual
             sampling model. We take this result as supporting evidence
             for existing Bayesian accounts of causal
             judgment.},
   Key = {fds369061}
}

@article{fds369062,
   Author = {Krasich, K and O'Neill, K and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Eye-tracking mental simulation during retrospective causal
             reasoning},
   Journal = {Proceedings of the 44th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive
             Science Society: Cognitive Diversity, CogSci
             2022},
   Pages = {1004-1010},
   Year = {2022},
   Month = {January},
   Abstract = {There are conflicting theories about how people reason
             through cause and effect. A key distinction between two
             prominent accounts pertains to whether, in judging an
             event's causal relevance, people preferentially consider
             what actually happened (as predicted by process theories) or
             whether they also consider what could have happened under
             different conditions (as predicted by counterfactual
             theories). Toward adjudicating between these theories, the
             current work used eye tracking and Gaussian Process modeling
             to investigate how people form causal judgments
             retrospectively and in the absence of ongoing visual input.
             Participants played a virtual ball-shooting game: after
             choosing to move left or right, they encoded a video of the
             actual outcome and then were prompted to mentally simulate
             either (a) what actually happened, (b) what could have
             happened, or (c) what caused the outcome to happen while
             looking at a blank screen. During causal judgment, we found
             evidence that participants visually mentally simulated
             counterfactual possibilities: they moved their eyes in
             similar patterns as when they imagined a counterfactual
             alternative. Altogether, these results favor counterfactual
             theories of causal reasoning, demonstrate how visual mental
             simulation can support this reasoning, and provide a novel
             methodological approach for using eye movements to
             investigate causal reasoning and counterfactual thinking
             more broadly.},
   Key = {fds369062}
}

@article{fds376732,
   Author = {Stanley, ML and De Brigard and FD},
   Title = {The Importance of Morality for One’s Self-Concept Predicts
             Perceptions of Personal Change after Remembering
             Wrongdoings},
   Pages = {143-156},
   Booktitle = {Experimental Philosophy of Identity and the
             Self},
   Year = {2022},
   Month = {January},
   ISBN = {9781350246898},
   Key = {fds376732}
}

@article{fds363370,
   Author = {Ayala, OD and Banta, D and Hovhannisyan, M and Duarte, L and Lozano, A and García, JR and Montañés, P and Davis, SW and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Episodic Past, Future, and counterfactual thinking in
             Relapsing-Remitting Multiple sclerosis.},
   Journal = {Neuroimage Clin},
   Volume = {34},
   Pages = {103033},
   Year = {2022},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.nicl.2022.103033},
   Abstract = {Multiple sclerosis (MS) is a progressive disease
             characterized by widespread white matter lesions in the
             brain and spinal cord. In addition to well-characterized
             motor deficits, MS results in cognitive impairments in
             several domains, notably in episodic autobiographical
             memory. Recent studies have also revealed that patients with
             MS exhibit deficits in episodic future thinking, i.e., our
             capacity to imagine possible events that may occur in our
             personal future. Both episodic memory and episodic future
             thinking have been shown to share cognitive and neural
             mechanisms with a related kind of hypothetical simulation
             known as episodic counterfactual thinking: our capacity to
             imagine alternative ways in which past personal events could
             have occurred but did not. However, the extent to which
             episodic counterfactual thinking is affected in MS is still
             unknown. The current study sought to explore this issue by
             comparing performance in mental simulation tasks involving
             either past, future or counterfactual thoughts in
             relapsing-remitting MS. Diffusion weighted imaging (DWI)
             measures were also extracted to determine whether changes in
             structural pathways connecting the brain's default mode
             network (DMN) would be associated with group differences in
             task performance. Relative to controls, patients showed
             marked reductions in the number of internal details across
             all mental simulations, but no differences in the number of
             external and semantic-based details. It was also found that,
             relative to controls, patients with relapsing-remitting MS
             reported reduced composition ratings for episodic
             simulations depicting counterfactual events, but not so for
             actual past or possible future episodes. Additionally, three
             DWI measures of white matter integrity-fractional
             anisotropy, radial diffusivity and streamline counts-showed
             reliable differences between patients with
             relapsing-remitting MS and matched healthy controls.
             Importantly, DWI measures associated with reduced white
             matter integrity in three association tracts on the DMN-the
             right superior longitudinal fasciculus, the left hippocampal
             portion of the cingulum and the left inferior longitudinal
             fasciculus-predicted reductions in the number of internal
             details during episodic counterfactual simulations. Taken
             together, these results help to illuminate impairments in
             episodic simulation in relapsing-remitting MS and show, for
             the first time, a differential association between white
             matter integrity and deficits in episodic counterfactual
             thinking in individuals with relapsing-remitting
             MS.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.nicl.2022.103033},
   Key = {fds363370}
}

@article{fds372919,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Sinnott-Armstrong, W},
   Title = {Neuroscience and Philosophy Introduction},
   Pages = {1-13},
   Booktitle = {NEUROSCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY},
   Year = {2022},
   ISBN = {978-0-262-04543-8},
   Key = {fds372919}
}

@article{fds359026,
   Author = {Gessell, B and Geib, B and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Multivariate pattern analysis and the search for neural
             representations},
   Journal = {Synthese},
   Volume = {199},
   Number = {5-6},
   Pages = {12869-12889},
   Year = {2021},
   Month = {December},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03358-3},
   Abstract = {Multivariate pattern analysis, or MVPA, has become one of
             the most popular analytic methods in cognitive neuroscience.
             Since its inception, MVPA has been heralded as offering much
             more than regular univariate analyses, for—we are
             told—it not only can tell us which brain regions are
             engaged while processing particular stimuli, but also which
             patterns of neural activity represent the categories the
             stimuli are selected from. We disagree, and in the current
             paper we offer four conceptual challenges to the use of MVPA
             to make claims about neural representation. Our view is that
             the use of MVPA to make claims about neural representation
             is problematic.},
   Doi = {10.1007/s11229-021-03358-3},
   Key = {fds359026}
}

@article{fds361803,
   Author = {Huang, S and Faul, L and Sevinc, G and Mwilambwe-Tshilobo, L and Setton,
             R and Lockrow, AW and Ebner, NC and Turner, GR and Spreng, RN and De
             Brigard, F},
   Title = {Age differences in intuitive moral decision-making:
             Associations with inter-network neural connectivity.},
   Journal = {Psychology and aging},
   Volume = {36},
   Number = {8},
   Pages = {902-916},
   Year = {2021},
   Month = {December},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/pag0000633},
   Abstract = {Positions of power involving moral decision-making are often
             held by older adults (OAs). However, little is known about
             age differences in moral decision-making and the intrinsic
             organization of the aging brain. In this study, younger
             adults (YAs; <i>n</i> = 117, <i>M</i><sub>age</sub> = 22.11)
             and OAs (<i>n</i> = 82, <i>M</i><sub>age</sub> = 67.54) made
             decisions in hypothetical moral dilemmas and completed
             resting-state multi-echo functional magnetic resonance
             imaging (fMRI) scans. Relative to YAs, OAs were more likely
             to endorse deontological decisions (i.e., decisions based on
             adherence to a moral principle or duty), but only when the
             choice was immediately compelling or <i>intuitive</i>. By
             contrast, there was no difference between YAs and OAs in
             utilitarian decisions (i.e., decisions aimed at maximizing
             collective well-being) when the utilitarian choice was
             intuitive. Enhanced connections between the posterior medial
             core of the default network (pmDN) and the dorsal attention
             network, and overall reduced segregation of pmDN from the
             rest of the brain, were associated with this increased
             deontological-intuitive moral decision-making style in OAs.
             The present study contributes to our understanding of age
             differences in decision-making styles by taking into account
             the intuitiveness of the moral choice, and it offers further
             insights as to how age differences in intrinsic brain
             connectivity relate to these distinct moral decision-making
             styles in YAs and OAs. (PsycInfo Database Record (c) 2021
             APA, all rights reserved).},
   Doi = {10.1037/pag0000633},
   Key = {fds361803}
}

@article{fds356451,
   Author = {Stanley, ML and Henne, P and Niemi, L and Sinnott-Armstrong, W and De
             Brigard, F},
   Title = {Making moral principles suit yourself.},
   Journal = {Psychonomic bulletin & review},
   Volume = {28},
   Number = {5},
   Pages = {1735-1741},
   Year = {2021},
   Month = {October},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.3758/s13423-021-01935-8},
   Abstract = {Normative ethical theories and religious traditions offer
             general moral principles for people to follow. These moral
             principles are typically meant to be fixed and rigid,
             offering reliable guides for moral judgment and
             decision-making. In two preregistered studies, we found
             consistent evidence that agreement with general moral
             principles shifted depending upon events recently accessed
             in memory. After recalling their own personal violations of
             moral principles, participants agreed less strongly with
             those very principles-relative to participants who recalled
             events in which other people violated the principles. This
             shift in agreement was explained, in part, by people's
             willingness to excuse their own moral transgressions, but
             not the transgressions of others. These results have
             important implications for understanding the roles memory
             and personal identity in moral judgment. People's commitment
             to moral principles may be maintained when they recall
             others' past violations, but their commitment may wane when
             they recall their own violations.},
   Doi = {10.3758/s13423-021-01935-8},
   Key = {fds356451}
}

@article{fds357557,
   Author = {Stanley, ML and Cabeza, R and Smallman, R and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Memory and Counterfactual Simulations for Past Wrongdoings
             Foster Moral Learning and Improvement.},
   Journal = {Cognitive science},
   Volume = {45},
   Number = {6},
   Pages = {e13007},
   Year = {2021},
   Month = {June},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/cogs.13007},
   Abstract = {In four studies, we investigated the role of remembering,
             reflecting on, and mutating personal past moral
             transgressions to learn from those moral mistakes and to
             form intentions for moral improvement. Participants reported
             having ruminated on their past wrongdoings, particularly
             their more severe transgressions, and they reported having
             frequently thought about morally better ways in which they
             could have acted instead (i.e., morally upward
             counterfactuals; Studies 1-3). The more that participants
             reported having mentally simulated morally better ways in
             which they could have acted, the stronger their intentions
             were to improve in the future (Studies 2 and 3).
             Implementing an experimental manipulation, we then found
             that making accessible a morally upward counterfactual after
             committing a moral transgression strengthened reported
             intentions for moral improvement-relative to resimulating
             the remembered event and considering morally worse ways in
             which they could have acted instead (Study 4). We discuss
             the implications of these results for competing theoretical
             views on the relationship between memory and morality and
             for functional theories of counterfactual
             thinking.},
   Doi = {10.1111/cogs.13007},
   Key = {fds357557}
}

@article{fds355019,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Henne, P and Stanley, ML},
   Title = {Perceived similarity of imagined possible worlds affects
             judgments of counterfactual plausibility.},
   Journal = {Cognition},
   Volume = {209},
   Pages = {104574},
   Year = {2021},
   Month = {April},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2020.104574},
   Abstract = {People frequently entertain counterfactual thoughts, or
             mental simulations about alternative ways the world could
             have been. But the perceived plausibility of those
             counterfactual thoughts varies widely. The current article
             interfaces research in the philosophy and semantics of
             counterfactual statements with the psychology of mental
             simulations, and it explores the role of perceived
             similarity in judgments of counterfactual plausibility. We
             report results from seven studies (N = 6405) jointly
             supporting three interconnected claims. First, the perceived
             plausibility of a counterfactual event is predicted by the
             perceived similarity between the possible world in which the
             imagined situation is thought to occur and the actual world.
             Second, when people attend to differences between imagined
             possible worlds and the actual world, they think of the
             imagined possible worlds as less similar to the actual world
             and tend to judge counterfactuals in such worlds as less
             plausible. Lastly, when people attend to what is identical
             between imagined possible worlds and the actual world, they
             think of the imagined possible worlds as more similar to the
             actual world and tend to judge counterfactuals in such
             worlds as more plausible. We discuss these results in light
             of philosophical, semantic, and psychological theories of
             counterfactual thinking.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.cognition.2020.104574},
   Key = {fds355019}
}

@article{fds372920,
   Author = {O'Neill, K and Henne, P and Bello, P and Pearson, J and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Confidence and Gradation in Causal Judgment},
   Year = {2021},
   Month = {February},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.31219/osf.io/m5w9c},
   Abstract = {<p>When comparing the roles of the lightning strike and the
             dry climate in causing the forest fire, one might think that
             the lightning strike is more of a cause than the dry
             climate, or one might think that the lightning strike
             completely caused the fire while the dry conditions did not
             cause it at all. Psychologists and philosophers have long
             debated whether such causal judgments are graded; that is,
             whether people treat some causes as stronger than others. To
             address this debate, we first reanalyzed data from four
             recent studies. We found that causal judgments were actually
             multimodal: although most causal judgments made on a
             continuous scale were categorical, there was also some
             gradation. We then tested two competing explanations for
             this gradation: the confidence explanation, which states
             that people make graded causal judgments because they have
             varying degrees of belief in causal relations, and the
             strength explanation, which states that people make graded
             causal judgments because they believe that causation itself
             is graded. Experiment 1 tested the confidence explanation
             and showed that gradation in causal judgments was indeed
             moderated by confidence: people tended to make graded causal
             judgments when they were unconfident, but they tended to
             make more categorical causal judgments when they were
             confident. Experiment 2 tested the causal strength
             explanation and showed that although confidence still
             explained variation in causal judgments, it did not explain
             away the effects of normality, causal structure, or the
             number of candidate causes. Overall, we found that causal
             judgments were multimodal and that people make graded
             judgments both when they think a cause is weak and when they
             are uncertain about its causal role.</p>},
   Doi = {10.31219/osf.io/m5w9c},
   Key = {fds372920}
}

@article{fds355198,
   Author = {Henne, P and O'Neill, K and Bello, P and Khemlani, S and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Norms Affect Prospective Causal Judgments.},
   Journal = {Cognitive science},
   Volume = {45},
   Number = {1},
   Pages = {e12931},
   Year = {2021},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12931},
   Abstract = {People more frequently select norm-violating factors,
             relative to norm-conforming ones, as the cause of some
             outcome. Until recently, this abnormal-selection effect has
             been studied using retrospective vignette-based paradigms.
             We use a novel set of video stimuli to investigate this
             effect for prospective causal judgments-that is, judgments
             about the cause of some future outcome. Four experiments
             show that people more frequently select norm-violating
             factors, relative to norm-conforming ones, as the cause of
             some future outcome. We show that the abnormal-selection
             effects are not primarily explained by the perception of
             agency (Experiment 4). We discuss these results in relation
             to recent efforts to model causal judgment.},
   Doi = {10.1111/cogs.12931},
   Key = {fds355198}
}

@article{fds356452,
   Author = {Gessell, B and Stanley, M and Geib, B and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Prediction and Topological Models in Neuroscience},
   Volume = {17},
   Pages = {35-55},
   Booktitle = {Studies in Brain and Mind},
   Year = {2021},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-54092-0_3},
   Abstract = {In the last two decades, philosophy of neuroscience has
             predominantly focused on explanation. Indeed, it has been
             argued that mechanistic models are the standards of
             explanatory success in neuroscience over, among other
             things, topological models. However, explanatory power is
             only one virtue of a scientific model. Another is its
             predictive power. Unfortunately, the notion of prediction
             has received comparatively little attention in the
             philosophy of neuroscience, in part because predictions seem
             disconnected from interventions. In contrast, we argue that
             topological predictions can and do guide interventions in
             science, both inside and outside of neuroscience.
             Topological models allow researchers to predict many
             phenomena, including diseases, treatment outcomes, aging,
             and cognition, among others. Moreover, we argue that these
             predictions also offer strategies for useful interventions.
             Topology-based predictions play this role regardless of
             whether they do or can receive a mechanistic interpretation.
             We conclude by making a case for philosophers to focus on
             prediction in neuroscience in addition to explanation
             alone.},
   Doi = {10.1007/978-3-030-54092-0_3},
   Key = {fds356452}
}

@article{fds361804,
   Author = {Parikh, N and De Brigard and F and LaBar, KS},
   Title = {The Efficacy of Downward Counterfactual Thinking for
             Regulating Emotional Memories in Anxious
             Individuals.},
   Journal = {Frontiers in psychology},
   Volume = {12},
   Pages = {712066},
   Year = {2021},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2021.712066},
   Abstract = {Aversive autobiographical memories sometimes prompt
             maladaptive emotional responses and contribute to affective
             dysfunction in anxiety and depression. One way to regulate
             the impact of such memories is to create a downward
             counterfactual thought-a mental simulation of how the event
             could have been worse-to put what occurred in a more
             positive light. Despite its intuitive appeal, counterfactual
             thinking has not been systematically studied for its
             regulatory efficacy. In the current study, we compared the
             regulatory impact of downward counterfactual thinking,
             temporal distancing, and memory rehearsal in 54 adult
             participants representing a spectrum of trait anxiety.
             Participants recalled regretful experiences and rated them
             on valence, arousal, regret, and episodic detail. Two to six
             days later, they created a downward counterfactual of the
             remembered event, thought of how they might feel about it 10
             years from now, or simply rehearsed it. A day later,
             participants re-rated the phenomenological characteristics
             of the events. Across all participants, downward
             counterfactual thinking, temporal distancing, and memory
             rehearsal were equally effective at reducing negative affect
             associated with a memory. However, in individuals with
             higher trait anxiety, downward counterfactual thinking was
             more effective than rehearsal for reducing regret, and it
             was as effective as distancing in reducing arousal. We
             discuss these results in light of the functional theory of
             counterfactual thinking and suggest that they motivate
             further investigation into downward counterfactual thinking
             as a means to intentionally regulate emotional memories in
             affective disorders.},
   Doi = {10.3389/fpsyg.2021.712066},
   Key = {fds361804}
}

@article{fds361924,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Stanley, ML},
   Title = {Moral Memories and Identity Protection},
   Journal = {Psychological Inquiry},
   Volume = {32},
   Number = {4},
   Pages = {240-246},
   Year = {2021},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1047840X.2021.2004817},
   Doi = {10.1080/1047840X.2021.2004817},
   Key = {fds361924}
}

@article{fds372921,
   Author = {O'Neill, K and Henne, P and Pearson, J and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Modeling Confidence in Causal Judgments},
   Year = {2021},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/cgvwf},
   Abstract = {<p>The human capacity for causal judgment has long been
             thought to depend on an ability to consider counterfactual
             alternatives: the lightning strike caused the forest fire
             because had it not struck, the forest fire would not have
             ensued. To accommodate psychological effects on causal
             judgment, a range of recent accounts of causal judgment have
             proposed that people probabilistically sample counterfactual
             alternatives from which they compute a graded index of
             causal strength. While such models have had success in
             describing the influence of probability on causal judgments,
             among other effects, we show that these models make further
             untested predictions: probability should also influence
             people's metacognitive confidence in their causal judgments.
             In a large (N=3020) sample of participants in a causal
             judgment task, we found evidence that normality indeed
             influences people's confidence in their causal judgments and
             that these influences were predicted by a counterfactual
             sampling model. We take this result as supporting evidence
             for existing Bayesian accounts of causal
             judgment.</p>},
   Doi = {10.31234/osf.io/cgvwf},
   Key = {fds372921}
}

@article{fds351193,
   Author = {Parikh, N and LaBar, KS and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Phenomenology of counterfactual thinking is dampened in
             anxious individuals.},
   Journal = {Cognition & emotion},
   Volume = {34},
   Number = {8},
   Pages = {1737-1745},
   Year = {2020},
   Month = {December},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02699931.2020.1802230},
   Abstract = {Counterfactual thinking (CFT), or simulating alternative
             versions of occurred events, is a common psychological
             strategy people use to process events in their lives.
             However, CFT is also a core component of ruminative thinking
             that contributes to psychopathology. Though prior studies
             have tried to distinguish adaptive from maladaptive CFT, our
             study provides a novel demonstration that identifies
             phenomenological differences across CFT in participants with
             varying levels of trait anxiety. Participants
             (<i>N </i>= 96) identified negative, regretful memories
             from the past 5 years and created a better counterfactual
             alternative (upward CFT), a worse counterfactual alternative
             (downward CFT), or simply recalled each memory. Participants
             with high levels of trait anxiety used more negative
             language when describing their mental simulations, reported
             lower ratings of composition during upward CFT, and reported
             more difficulty in imagining the emotion they would have
             felt had negative events turned out to be better.
             Additionally, participants with high anxiety thought that
             upward CFT was less likely to occur relative to individuals
             with low anxiety. These results help to clarify how mental
             simulations of aversive life events are altered in anxiety
             and serve as a stepping stone to future research uncovering
             the mechanisms of ruminative thought patterns.},
   Doi = {10.1080/02699931.2020.1802230},
   Key = {fds351193}
}

@article{fds341028,
   Author = {Stanley, ML and Henne, P and Yang, BW and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Resistance to Position Change, Motivated Reasoning, and
             Polarization},
   Journal = {Political Behavior},
   Volume = {42},
   Number = {3},
   Pages = {891-913},
   Year = {2020},
   Month = {September},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11109-019-09526-z},
   Abstract = {People seem more divided than ever before over social and
             political issues, entrenched in their existing beliefs and
             unwilling to change them. Empirical research on mechanisms
             driving this resistance to belief change has focused on a
             limited set of well-known, charged, contentious issues and
             has not accounted for deliberation over reasons and
             arguments in belief formation prior to experimental
             sessions. With a large, heterogeneous sample (N = 3001),
             we attempt to overcome these existing problems, and we
             investigate the causes and consequences of resistance to
             belief change for five diverse and less contentious
             socio-political issues. After participants chose initially
             to support or oppose a given socio-political position, they
             were provided with reasons favoring their chosen position
             (affirming reasons), reasons favoring the other, unchosen
             position (conflicting reasons), or all reasons for both
             positions (reasons for both sides). Our results indicate
             that participants are more likely to stick with their
             initial decisions than to change them no matter which
             reasons are considered, and that this resistance to belief
             change is likely due to a motivated, biased evaluation of
             the reasons to support their initial beliefs (prior-belief
             bias). More specifically, they rated affirming reasons more
             favorably than conflicting reasons—even after accounting
             for reported prior knowledge about the issue, the novelty of
             the reasons presented, and the reported strategy used to
             make the initial decision. In many cases, participants who
             did not change their positions tended to become more
             confident in the superiority of their positions after
             considering many reasons for both sides.},
   Doi = {10.1007/s11109-019-09526-z},
   Key = {fds341028}
}

@article{fds349388,
   Author = {Faul, L and St Jacques and PL and DeRosa, JT and Parikh, N and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Differential contribution of anterior and posterior midline
             regions during mental simulation of counterfactual and
             perspective shifts in autobiographical memories.},
   Journal = {NeuroImage},
   Volume = {215},
   Pages = {116843},
   Year = {2020},
   Month = {July},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.neuroimage.2020.116843},
   Abstract = {Retrieving autobiographical memories induces a natural
             tendency to mentally simulate alternate versions of past
             events, either by reconstructing the perceptual details of
             the originally experienced perspective or the conceptual
             information of what actually occurred. Here we examined
             whether the episodic system recruited during imaginative
             experiences functionally dissociates depending on the nature
             of this reconstruction. Using fMRI, we evaluated
             differential patterns of neural activity and hippocampal
             connectivity when twenty-nine participants naturally
             recalled past negative events, shifted visual perspective,
             or imagined better or worse outcomes than what actually
             occurred. We found that counterfactual thoughts were
             distinguished by neural recruitment in dorsomedial
             prefrontal cortex, whereas shifts in visual perspective were
             uniquely supported by the precuneus. Additionally,
             connectivity with the anterior hippocampus changed depending
             upon the mental simulation that was performed - with
             enhanced hippocampal connectivity with medial prefrontal
             cortex for counterfactual simulations and precuneus for
             shifted visual perspectives. Together, our findings provide
             a novel assessment of differences between these common
             methods of mental simulation and a more detailed account for
             the neural network underlying episodic retrieval and
             reconstruction.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.neuroimage.2020.116843},
   Key = {fds349388}
}

@article{fds342766,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Langella, S and Stanley, ML and Castel, AD and Giovanello, KS},
   Title = {Age-related differences in recognition in associative
             memory.},
   Journal = {Neuropsychology, development, and cognition. Section B,
             Aging, neuropsychology and cognition},
   Volume = {27},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {289-301},
   Year = {2020},
   Month = {March},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13825585.2019.1607820},
   Abstract = {Aging is often accompanied by associative memory changes,
             although their precise nature remains unclear. This study
             examines how recognition of item position in the context of
             associative memory differs between younger and older adults.
             Participants studied word pairs (A-B, C-D) and were later
             tested with intact (A-B), reversed (D-C), recombined (A-D),
             and recombined and reversed (B-C) pairs. When participants
             were instructed to respond "Old" to both intact and reversed
             pairs, and "New" to recombined, and recombined and reversed
             pairs, older adults showed worse recognition for recombined
             and reversed pairs relative to younger adults (Experiment
             1). This finding also emerged when flexible retrieval
             demands were increased by asking participants to respond
             "Old" <i>only</i> to intact pairs (Experiment 2). These
             results suggest that as conditions for flexible retrieval
             become more demanding, older adults may show worse
             recognition in associative memory tasks relative to younger
             adults.},
   Doi = {10.1080/13825585.2019.1607820},
   Key = {fds342766}
}

@article{fds348484,
   Author = {Stanley, ML and Bedrov, A and Cabeza, R and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {The centrality of remembered moral and immoral actions in
             constructing personal identity.},
   Journal = {Memory (Hove, England)},
   Volume = {28},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {278-284},
   Year = {2020},
   Month = {February},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09658211.2019.1708952},
   Abstract = {There is a widespread belief that morally good traits and
             qualities are particularly central to psychological
             constructions of personal identity. People have a strong
             tendency to believe that they truly are morally good. We
             suggest that autobiographical memories of past events
             involving moral actions may inform how we come to believe
             that we are morally good. In two studies, we investigated
             the role of remembered past events involving moral and
             immoral actions in constructing perceived personal identity.
             For morally right actions only, we found that remembered
             actions judged to be more morally right relative to less
             morally right were more central to personal identity (Study
             1). We then found that remembered morally right actions were
             more central to personal identity than remembered morally
             wrong actions (Study 2). We discuss these findings in
             relation to recent research on morality and personal
             identity.},
   Doi = {10.1080/09658211.2019.1708952},
   Key = {fds348484}
}

@article{fds366567,
   Author = {Huang, S and Stanley, ML and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {The phenomenology of remembering our moral
             transgressions.},
   Journal = {Memory & cognition},
   Volume = {48},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {277-286},
   Year = {2020},
   Month = {February},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.3758/s13421-019-01009-0},
   Abstract = {People tend to believe that they truly are morally good, and
             yet they commit moral transgressions with surprising
             frequency in their everyday lives. To explain this
             phenomenon, some theorists have suggested that people
             remember their moral transgressions with fewer details,
             lower vivacity, and less clarity, relative to their morally
             good deeds and other kinds of past events. These
             phenomenological differences are thought to help alleviate
             psychological discomfort and to help people maintain a
             morally good self-concept. Given these motivations to
             alleviate discomfort and to maintain a morally good
             self-concept, we might expect our more egregious moral
             transgressions, relative to our more minor transgressions,
             to be remembered less frequently, with fewer details, with
             lower vivacity, and with a reduced sense of reliving. More
             severe moral transgressions might also be less central to
             constructions of personal identity. In contrast to these
             expectations, our results suggest that participants' more
             severe moral transgressions are actually remembered more
             frequently, more vividly, and with more detail. More severe
             moral transgressions also tend to be more central to
             personal identity. We discuss the implications of these
             results for the motivation to maintain a morally good
             self-concept and for the functions of autobiographical
             memory.},
   Doi = {10.3758/s13421-019-01009-0},
   Key = {fds366567}
}

@article{fds349624,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Gessell, B and Yang, BW and Stewart, G and Marsh,
             EJ},
   Title = {Remembering possible times: Memory for details of past,
             future, and counterfactual simulations.},
   Journal = {Psychology of Consciousness: Theory Research, and
             Practice},
   Volume = {7},
   Number = {4},
   Pages = {331-339},
   Year = {2020},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/cns0000220},
   Abstract = {People’s capacity to mentally simulate future events
             (episodic future thinking) as well as what could have
             occurred in the past but did not (episodic counterfactual
             thinking) critically depends on their capacity to retrieve
             episodic memories. All 3 mental simulations are likely
             adaptive in that they involve rehearsing possible scenarios
             with the goal of improving future performance. However, the
             extent to which these mental simulations are useful at a
             later time depends on how well they are later remembered.
             Unfortunately, little is known about how such simulations
             are remembered. In the current study, we explored this issue
             by asking participants to retrieve episodic memories and
             generate future and counterfactual simulations in response
             to 4 cues: particular places, people, objects, and times. A
             day later participants received 3 of the 4 cues and were
             asked to recall the remaining 1. Our results indicate that
             people and locations are equally well remembered, regardless
             of the temporal orientation of the mental simulation. In
             contrast, objects in future simulations are recalled less
             frequently than are those in memories. Time was poorly
             remembered across conditions but especially when remembering
             a future or a counterfactual simulation. In light of these
             results, we discuss how temporal information may be
             incorporated into our hypothetical episodic simulations.
             (PsycInfo Database Record (c) 2020 APA, all rights
             reserved)},
   Doi = {10.1037/cns0000220},
   Key = {fds349624}
}

@article{fds354585,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Do we need another kind of memory?},
   Journal = {Journal of Consciousness Studies},
   Volume = {27},
   Number = {11-12},
   Pages = {134-144},
   Year = {2020},
   Month = {January},
   Key = {fds354585}
}

@article{fds372922,
   Author = {Henne, P and O'Neill, K and Bello, P and Khemlani, S and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Norms Affect Prospective Causal Judgments},
   Year = {2019},
   Month = {December},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.31219/osf.io/2nwb4},
   Abstract = {<p>People more frequently select norm-violating factors,
             relative to norm-conforming ones, as the cause of some
             outcome. Until recently, this abnormal-selection effect has
             been studied using retrospective vignette-based paradigms.
             We use a novel set of video stimuli to investigate this
             effect for prospective causal judgments—i.e., judgments
             about the cause of some future outcome. Four experiments
             show that people more frequently select norm-violating
             factors, relative to norm-conforming ones, as the cause of
             some future outcome. We show that the abnormal-selection
             effects are not primarily explained by the perception of
             agency (Experiment 4). We discuss these results in relation
             to recent efforts to model causal judgment.</p>},
   Doi = {10.31219/osf.io/2nwb4},
   Key = {fds372922}
}

@article{fds347639,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and O'Neill, K},
   Title = {Two challenges for a dual system approach to temporal
             cognition.},
   Journal = {The Behavioral and brain sciences},
   Volume = {42},
   Pages = {e247},
   Year = {2019},
   Month = {December},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0140525x19000645},
   Abstract = {Hoerl & McCormack (H&M) propose a two-system account of
             temporal cognition. We suggest that, following other classic
             proposals where cognitive systems are putatively
             independent, H&M's two-system hypothesis should, at a
             minimum, involve (1) a difference in the nature of the
             representations upon which each system operates, and (2) a
             difference in the computations they carry out. In this
             comment we offer two challenges aimed at showing that H&M's
             proposal does not meet the minimal requirements (1) and
             (2).},
   Doi = {10.1017/s0140525x19000645},
   Key = {fds347639}
}

@article{fds343341,
   Author = {Henne, P and Niemi, L and Pinillos, Á and De Brigard and F and Knobe,
             J},
   Title = {A counterfactual explanation for the action effect in causal
             judgment.},
   Journal = {Cognition},
   Volume = {190},
   Pages = {157-164},
   Year = {2019},
   Month = {September},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2019.05.006},
   Abstract = {People's causal judgments are susceptible to the action
             effect, whereby they judge actions to be more causal than
             inactions. We offer a new explanation for this effect, the
             counterfactual explanation: people judge actions to be more
             causal than inactions because they are more inclined to
             consider the counterfactual alternatives to actions than to
             consider counterfactual alternatives to inactions.
             Experiment 1a conceptually replicates the original action
             effect for causal judgments. Experiment 1b confirms a novel
             prediction of the new explanation, the reverse action
             effect, in which people judge inactions to be more causal
             than actions in overdetermination cases. Experiment 2
             directly compares the two effects in joint-causation and
             overdetermination scenarios and conceptually replicates them
             with new scenarios. Taken together, these studies provide
             support for the new counterfactual explanation for the
             action effect in causal judgment.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.cognition.2019.05.006},
   Key = {fds343341}
}

@article{fds343711,
   Author = {Stanley, ML and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Moral Memories and the Belief in the Good
             Self},
   Journal = {Current Directions in Psychological Science},
   Volume = {28},
   Number = {4},
   Pages = {387-391},
   Year = {2019},
   Month = {August},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0963721419847990},
   Abstract = {Most people believe they are morally good, and this belief
             plays an integral role in constructions of personal
             identity. Yet people commit moral transgressions with
             surprising frequency in everyday life. In this article, we
             characterize two mechanisms involving autobiographical
             memory that are utilized to foster a belief in a morally
             good self in the present—despite frequent and repeated
             immoral behavior. First, there is a tendency for people to
             willfully and actively forget details about their own moral
             transgressions but not about their own morally praiseworthy
             deeds. Second, when past moral transgressions are not
             forgotten, people strategically compare their more recent
             unethical behaviors with their more distant unethical
             behaviors to foster a perception of personal moral
             improvement over time. This, in turn, helps to portray the
             current self favorably. These two complementary mechanisms
             help to explain pervasive inconsistencies between people’s
             personal beliefs about their own moral goodness and the
             frequency with which they behave immorally.},
   Doi = {10.1177/0963721419847990},
   Key = {fds343711}
}

@article{fds335559,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Hanna, E and St Jacques and PL and Schacter,
             DL},
   Title = {How thinking about what could have been affects how we feel
             about what was.},
   Journal = {Cognition & emotion},
   Volume = {33},
   Number = {4},
   Pages = {646-659},
   Publisher = {Informa UK Limited},
   Year = {2019},
   Month = {June},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02699931.2018.1478280},
   Abstract = {Episodic counterfactual thoughts (CFT) and autobiographical
             memories (AM) involve the reactivation and recombination of
             episodic memory components into mental simulations. Upon
             reactivation, memories become labile and prone to
             modification. Thus, reactivating AM in the context of
             mentally generating CFT may provide an opportunity for
             editing processes to modify the content of the original
             memory. To examine this idea, this paper reports the results
             of two studies that investigated the effect of reactivating
             negative and positive AM in the context of either imagining
             a better (i.e. upward CFT) or a worse (i.e. downward CFT)
             alternative to an experienced event, as opposed to
             attentively retrieving the memory without mental
             modification (i.e. remembering) or no reactivation. Our
             results suggest that attentive remembering was the best
             strategy to both reduce the negative affect associated with
             negative AM, and to prevent the decay of positive affect
             associated with positive AM. In addition, reactivating
             positive, but not negative, AM with or without CFT
             modification reduces the perceived arousal of the original
             memory over time. Finally, reactivating negative AM in a
             downward CFT or an attentive remembering condition increases
             the perceived detail of the original memory over
             time.},
   Doi = {10.1080/02699931.2018.1478280},
   Key = {fds335559}
}

@article{fds332864,
   Author = {Murray, S and Murray, ED and Stewart, G and Sinnott-Armstrong, W and De
             Brigard, F},
   Title = {Responsibility for forgetting},
   Journal = {Philosophical Studies},
   Volume = {176},
   Number = {5},
   Pages = {1177-1201},
   Publisher = {Springer Nature},
   Year = {2019},
   Month = {May},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1053-3},
   Abstract = {In this paper, we focus on whether and to what extent we
             judge that people are responsible for the consequences of
             their forgetfulness. We ran a series of behavioral studies
             to measure judgments of responsibility for the consequences
             of forgetfulness. Our results show that we are disposed to
             hold others responsible for some of their forgetfulness. The
             level of stress that the forgetful agent is under modulates
             judgments of responsibility, though the level of care that
             the agent exhibits toward performing the forgotten action
             does not. We argue that this result has important
             implications for a long-running debate about the nature of
             responsible agency.},
   Doi = {10.1007/s11098-018-1053-3},
   Key = {fds332864}
}

@article{fds341029,
   Author = {Stanley, ML and Henne, P and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Remembering moral and immoral actions in constructing the
             self.},
   Journal = {Memory & cognition},
   Volume = {47},
   Number = {3},
   Pages = {441-454},
   Year = {2019},
   Month = {April},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.3758/s13421-018-0880-y},
   Abstract = {Having positive moral traits is central to one's sense of
             self, and people generally are motivated to maintain a
             positive view of the self in the present. But it remains
             unclear how people foster a positive, morally good view of
             the self in the present. We suggest that recollecting and
             reflecting on moral and immoral actions from the personal
             past jointly help to construct a morally good view of the
             current self in complementary ways. More specifically,
             across four studies we investigated the extent to which
             people believe they have changed over time after
             recollecting their own moral or immoral behaviors from the
             personal past. Our results indicate that recollecting past
             immoral actions is associated with stronger impressions of
             dissimilarity and change in the sense of self over time than
             recollecting past moral actions. These effects held for
             diverse domains of morality (i.e., honesty/dishonesty,
             helping/harming, fairness/unfairness, and
             loyalty/disloyalty), and they remained even after accounting
             for objective, calendar time. Further supporting a
             motivational explanation, these effects held when people
             recollected their own past actions but not when they
             recollected the actions of other people.},
   Doi = {10.3758/s13421-018-0880-y},
   Key = {fds341029}
}

@article{fds341881,
   Author = {Henne, P and Semler, J and Chituc, V and De Brigard and F and Sinnott-Armstrong, W},
   Title = {Against Some Recent Arguments for ‘Ought’ Implies
             ‘Can’: Reasons, Deliberation, Trying, and
             Furniture},
   Journal = {Philosophia (United States)},
   Volume = {47},
   Number = {1},
   Pages = {131-139},
   Year = {2019},
   Month = {March},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9944-7},
   Abstract = {Many philosophers claim that ‘ought’ implies ‘can’.
             In light of recent empirical evidence, however, some
             skeptics conclude that philosophers should stop assuming the
             principle unconditionally. Streumer, however, does not
             simply assume the principle’s truth; he provides arguments
             for it. In this article, we argue that his arguments fail to
             support the claim that ‘ought’ implies
             ‘can’.},
   Doi = {10.1007/s11406-017-9944-7},
   Key = {fds341881}
}

@article{fds341030,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Parikh, N},
   Title = {Episodic Counterfactual Thinking},
   Journal = {Current Directions in Psychological Science},
   Volume = {28},
   Number = {1},
   Pages = {59-66},
   Year = {2019},
   Month = {February},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0963721418806512},
   Abstract = {Our tendency to engage in episodic counterfactual
             thinking—namely, imagining alternative ways in which past
             personal events could have occurred but did not—is
             ubiquitous. Although widely studied by cognitive and social
             psychologists, this autobiographically based variety of
             counterfactual thought has been connected only recently to
             research on the cognitive and neuroscientific basis of
             episodic memory and mental simulation. In the current
             article, we offer an empirical characterization of episodic
             counterfactual thinking by contrasting it with related
             varieties of mental simulation along three dimensions:
             temporal context, degree of episodic detail, and modal
             profile (i.e., perceived possibility or impossibility). In
             so doing, we offer a practical strategy to navigate the
             nascent literature on episodic counterfactual thinking
             within the context of other mental simulations, and we argue
             that the evidence surveyed strongly indicates that although
             connected along the aforementioned dimensions, episodic
             counterfactual thinking is a psychological process different
             from episodic memory, episodic future thinking, and semantic
             counterfactual thinking.},
   Doi = {10.1177/0963721418806512},
   Key = {fds341030}
}

@article{fds341027,
   Author = {Stanley, ML and Gessell, B and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Network modularity as a foundation for neural
             reuse},
   Journal = {Philosophy of Science},
   Volume = {86},
   Number = {1},
   Pages = {23-46},
   Year = {2019},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/701037},
   Abstract = {The neural reuse framework developed primarily by Michael
             Anderson proposes that brain regions are involved in
             multiple and diverse cognitive tasks and that brain regions
             flexibly and dynamically interact in different combinations
             to carry out cognitive functioning. We argue that the
             evidence cited by Anderson and others falls short of
             supporting the fundamental principles of neural reuse. We
             map out this problem and provide solutions by drawing on
             recent advances in network neuroscience, and we argue that
             methods employed in network neuroscience provide the means
             to fully engage in a research program operating under the
             principles of neural reuse.},
   Doi = {10.1086/701037},
   Key = {fds341027}
}

@article{fds345881,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Know-how, intellectualism, and memory systems},
   Journal = {Philosophical Psychology},
   Volume = {32},
   Number = {5},
   Pages = {719-758},
   Year = {2019},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2019.1607280},
   Abstract = {A longstanding tradition in philosophy distinguishes between
             knowthatand know-how. This traditional “anti-intellectualist”
             view is soentrenched in folk psychology that it is often
             invoked in supportof an allegedly equivalent distinction
             between explicit and implicitmemory, derived from the
             so-called “standard model of memory.”In the last two
             decades, the received philosophical view has beenchallenged
             by an “intellectualist” view of know-how. Surprisingly,
             defenders of the anti-intellectualist view have turned to
             the cognitivescience of memory, and to the standard model in
             particular, todefend their view. Here, I argue that this
             strategy is a mistake. As it turns out, upon closer
             scrutiny, the evidence from cognitivepsychology and
             neuroscience of memory does not support theanti-intellectualist
             approach, mainly because the standard modelof memory is
             likely wrong. However, this need not be interpretedas good
             news for the intellectualist, for it is not clear that
             theempirical evidence necessarily supports their view
             either. I arguethat, currently, the philosophical debate is
             couched in terms thatdo not correspond to categories in
             psychological science. As aresult, the debate has to either
             be re-interpreted in a vocabularythat is amenable to
             experimental scrutiny, or it cannot be settledempirically.},
   Doi = {10.1080/09515089.2019.1607280},
   Key = {fds345881}
}

@article{fds345882,
   Author = {Pavese, C and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Editor’s introduction},
   Journal = {Philosophical Psychology},
   Volume = {32},
   Number = {5},
   Pages = {585-587},
   Year = {2019},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2019.1607964},
   Doi = {10.1080/09515089.2019.1607964},
   Key = {fds345882}
}

@article{fds367332,
   Author = {Henne, P and Bello, P and Khemlani, S and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Norms and the meaning of omissive enabling
             conditions},
   Journal = {Proceedings of the 41st Annual Meeting of the Cognitive
             Science Society: Creativity + Cognition + Computation,
             CogSci 2019},
   Pages = {1901-1907},
   Year = {2019},
   Month = {January},
   ISBN = {9780991196777},
   Abstract = {People often reason about omissions. One line of research
             shows that people can distinguish between the semantics of
             omissive causes and omissive enabling conditions: for
             instance, not flunking out of college enabled you (but
             didn't cause you) to graduate. Another line of work shows
             that people rely on the normative status of omissive events
             in inferring their causal role: if the outcome came about
             because the omission violated some norm, reasoners are more
             likely to select that omission as a cause. We designed a
             novel paradigm that tests how norms interact with the
             semantics of omissive enabling conditions. The paradigm
             concerns the circuitry of a mechanical device that plays
             music. Two experiments used the paradigm to stipulate norms
             and present a distinct set of possibilities to participants.
             Participants chose which causal verb best described the
             operations of the machine. The studies revealed that
             participants' responses are best predicted by their tendency
             to consider the semantics of omissive relations. In
             contrast, norms had little to no effect in participants'
             responses. We conclude by marshaling the evidence and
             considering what role norms may play in people's
             understanding of omissions.},
   Key = {fds367332}
}

@article{fds367333,
   Author = {Yin, S and O'Neill, K and Brady, TF and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {The Effect for Category Learning on Recognition Memory: A
             Signal Detection Theory Analysis},
   Journal = {Proceedings of the 41st Annual Meeting of the Cognitive
             Science Society: Creativity + Cognition + Computation,
             CogSci 2019},
   Pages = {3165-3171},
   Year = {2019},
   Month = {January},
   ISBN = {9780991196777},
   Abstract = {Previous studies have shown that category learning affects
             subsequent recognition memory. However, questions remain as
             to how category learning affects discriminability during
             recognition. In this three-stage study, we employed sets of
             simulated flowers with category- and non-category-inclusion
             features appearing with equal probabilities. In the learning
             stage, participants were asked to categorize flowers by
             identifying the category-inclusion feature. Next, in the
             studying stage, participants memorized a new set of flowers,
             a third of which belonged to the learned category. Finally,
             in the testing stage, participants received a recognition
             test with old and new flowers, some from the learned
             category, some from a not-learned category, some from both
             categories, and some from neither category. We applied
             hierarchical Bayesian signal detection theory models to
             recognition performance and found that prior category
             learning affected both discriminability as well as criterion
             bias. That is, people that learned the category well,
             exhibited improved discriminability and a shifted bias
             toward flowers from the learned relative to the not learned
             category.},
   Key = {fds367333}
}

@article{fds335558,
   Author = {Parikh, N and Ruzic, L and Stewart, GW and Spreng, RN and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {What if? Neural activity underlying semantic and episodic
             counterfactual thinking.},
   Journal = {NeuroImage},
   Volume = {178},
   Pages = {332-345},
   Year = {2018},
   Month = {September},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.neuroimage.2018.05.053},
   Abstract = {Counterfactual thinking (CFT) is the process of mentally
             simulating alternative versions of known facts. In the past
             decade, cognitive neuroscientists have begun to uncover the
             neural underpinnings of CFT, particularly episodic CFT
             (eCFT), which activates regions in the default network (DN)
             also activated by episodic memory (eM) recall. However, the
             engagement of DN regions is different for distinct kinds of
             eCFT. More plausible counterfactuals and counterfactuals
             about oneself show stronger activity in DN regions compared
             to implausible and other- or object-focused counterfactuals.
             The current study sought to identify a source for this
             difference in DN activity. Specifically, self-focused
             counterfactuals may also be more plausible, suggesting that
             DN core regions are sensitive to the plausibility of a
             simulation. On the other hand, plausible and self-focused
             counterfactuals may involve more episodic information than
             implausible and other-focused counterfactuals, which would
             imply DN sensitivity to episodic information. In the current
             study, we compared episodic and semantic counterfactuals
             generated to be plausible or implausible against episodic
             and semantic memory reactivation using fMRI. Taking
             multivariate and univariate approaches, we found that the DN
             is engaged more during episodic simulations, including eM
             and all eCFT, than during semantic simulations. Semantic
             simulations engaged more inferior temporal and lateral
             occipital regions. The only region that showed strong
             plausibility effects was the hippocampus, which was
             significantly engaged for implausible CFT but not for
             plausible CFT, suggestive of binding more disparate
             information. Consequences of these findings for the
             cognitive neuroscience of mental simulation are
             discussed.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.neuroimage.2018.05.053},
   Key = {fds335558}
}

@article{fds336415,
   Author = {Stanley, ML and Yang, BW and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {No evidence for unethical amnesia for imagined actions: A
             failed replication and extension.},
   Journal = {Memory & cognition},
   Volume = {46},
   Number = {5},
   Pages = {787-795},
   Publisher = {Springer Nature},
   Year = {2018},
   Month = {July},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.3758/s13421-018-0803-y},
   Abstract = {In a recent study, Kouchaki and Gino (2016) suggest that
             memory for unethical actions is impaired, regardless of
             whether such actions are real or imagined. However, as we
             argue in the current study, their claim that people develop
             "unethical amnesia" confuses two distinct and dissociable
             memory deficits: one affecting the phenomenology of
             remembering and another affecting memory accuracy. To
             further investigate whether unethical amnesia affects memory
             accuracy, we conducted three studies exploring unethical
             amnesia for imagined ethical violations. The first study (N
             = 228) attempts to directly replicate the only study from
             Kouchaki and Gino (2016) that includes a measure of memory
             accuracy. The second study (N = 232) attempts again to
             replicate these accuracy effects from Kouchaki and Gino
             (2016), while including several additional variables meant
             to potentially help in finding the effect. The third study
             (N = 228) is an attempted conceptual replication using the
             same paradigm as Kouchaki and Gino (2016), but with a new
             vignette describing a different moral violation. We did not
             find an unethical amnesia effect involving memory accuracy
             in any of our three studies. These results cast doubt upon
             the claim that memory accuracy is impaired for imagined
             unethical actions. Suggestions for further ways to study
             memory for moral and immoral actions are
             discussed.},
   Doi = {10.3758/s13421-018-0803-y},
   Key = {fds336415}
}

@article{fds329104,
   Author = {Stanley, ML and Dougherty, AM and Yang, BW and Henne, P and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Reasons probably won't change your mind: The role of reasons
             in revising moral decisions.},
   Journal = {Journal of experimental psychology. General},
   Volume = {147},
   Number = {7},
   Pages = {962-987},
   Year = {2018},
   Month = {July},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/xge0000368},
   Abstract = {Although many philosophers argue that making and revising
             moral decisions ought to be a matter of deliberating over
             reasons, the extent to which the consideration of reasons
             informs people's moral decisions and prompts them to change
             their decisions remains unclear. Here, after making an
             initial decision in 2-option moral dilemmas, participants
             examined reasons for only the option initially chosen
             (affirming reasons), reasons for only the option not
             initially chosen (opposing reasons), or reasons for both
             options. Although participants were more likely to change
             their initial decisions when presented with only opposing
             reasons compared with only affirming reasons, these effect
             sizes were consistently small. After evaluating reasons,
             participants were significantly more likely not to change
             their initial decisions than to change them, regardless of
             the set of reasons they considered. The initial decision
             accounted for most of the variance in predicting the final
             decision, whereas the reasons evaluated accounted for a
             relatively small proportion of the variance in predicting
             the final decision. This resistance to changing moral
             decisions is at least partly attributable to a biased,
             motivated evaluation of the available reasons: participants
             rated the reasons supporting their initial decisions more
             favorably than the reasons opposing their initial decisions,
             regardless of the reported strategy used to make the initial
             decision. Overall, our results suggest that the
             consideration of reasons rarely induces people to change
             their initial decisions in moral dilemmas. (PsycINFO
             Database Record},
   Doi = {10.1037/xge0000368},
   Key = {fds329104}
}

@article{fds335560,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Brady, WJ},
   Title = {Correction to: The Effect of What We Think may Happen on our
             Judgments of Responsibility (Review of Philosophy and
             Psychology, (2013), 4, 2, (259-269), 10.1007/s13164-013-0133-8)},
   Journal = {Review of Philosophy and Psychology},
   Volume = {9},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {447},
   Publisher = {Springer Nature},
   Year = {2018},
   Month = {June},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s13164-018-0389-0},
   Abstract = {On pages 263, 265, and 266, incorrect degrees of freedom and
             t values were reported. The statistical conclusions are not
             affected by these reporting errors, but the corrected values
             are shown below.},
   Doi = {10.1007/s13164-018-0389-0},
   Key = {fds335560}
}

@article{fds335561,
   Author = {De Freitas and J and Sarkissian, H and Newman, GE and Grossmann, I and De
             Brigard, F and Luco, A and Knobe, J},
   Title = {Consistent Belief in a Good True Self in Misanthropes and
             Three Interdependent Cultures.},
   Journal = {Cognitive science},
   Volume = {42 Suppl 1},
   Pages = {134-160},
   Year = {2018},
   Month = {May},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12505},
   Abstract = {People sometimes explain behavior by appealing to an
             essentialist concept of the self, often referred to as the
             true self. Existing studies suggest that people tend to
             believe that the true self is morally virtuous; that is deep
             inside, every person is motivated to behave in morally good
             ways. Is this belief particular to individuals with
             optimistic beliefs or people from Western cultures, or does
             it reflect a widely held cognitive bias in how people
             understand the self? To address this question, we tested the
             good true self theory against two potential boundary
             conditions that are known to elicit different beliefs about
             the self as a whole. Study 1 tested whether individual
             differences in misanthropy-the tendency to view humans
             negatively-predict beliefs about the good true self in an
             American sample. The results indicate a consistent belief in
             a good true self, even among individuals who have an
             explicitly pessimistic view of others. Study 2 compared true
             self-attributions across cultural groups, by comparing
             samples from an independent country (USA) and a diverse set
             of interdependent countries (Russia, Singapore, and
             Colombia). Results indicated that the direction and
             magnitude of the effect are comparable across all groups we
             tested. The belief in a good true self appears robust across
             groups varying in cultural orientation or misanthropy,
             suggesting a consistent psychological tendency to view the
             true self as morally good.},
   Doi = {10.1111/cogs.12505},
   Key = {fds335561}
}

@article{fds372923,
   Author = {Stanley, M and Yang, B and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {No Evidence for Unethical Amnesia for Imagined Actions: A
             Failed Replication and Extension},
   Year = {2018},
   Month = {March},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/kn8ce},
   Abstract = {<p>In a recent paper, Kouchaki and Gino (2016) suggest that
             memory for unethical actions is impaired, regardless of
             whether such actions are real or imagined. However, as we
             argue in the current paper, their claim that people develop
             “unethical amnesia” confuses two distinct and
             dissociable memory deficits: one affecting the phenomenology
             of remembering and another affecting memory accuracy. To
             further investigate whether unethical amnesia affects memory
             accuracy, we conducted three studies exploring unethical
             amnesia for imagined ethical violations. The first study (N
             = 228) attempts to directly replicate the only study from
             Kouchaki and Gino (2016) that includes a measure of memory
             accuracy. The second study (N = 232) attempts again to
             replicate these accuracy effects from Kouchaki and Gino
             (2016), while including several additional variables meant
             to potentially help in finding the effect. The third study
             (N = 228) is an attempted conceptual replication using the
             same paradigm as Kouchaki and Gino (2016), but with a new
             vignette describing a different moral violation. We did not
             find an unethical amnesia effect involving memory accuracy
             in any of our three studies. These results cast doubt upon
             the claim that memory accuracy is impaired for imagined
             unethical actions. Suggestions for further ways to study
             memory for moral and immoral actions are
             discussed.</p>},
   Doi = {10.31234/osf.io/kn8ce},
   Key = {fds372923}
}

@article{fds337053,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Memory and the intentional stance},
   Pages = {62-91},
   Booktitle = {The Philosophy of Daniel Dennett},
   Publisher = {Oxford University Press},
   Year = {2018},
   Month = {February},
   ISBN = {9780199367511},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780199367511.003.0005},
   Abstract = {Despite Dennett's vast scholarship, he seemed to only have
             directly addressed the topic of memory in a relatively
             unknown coauthored article published in a somewhat obscure
             volume. The current chapter attempts to reconstruct the
             ideas from this old article, and argues that it offers a
             viable and coherent view of episodic memory with substantial
             empirical support. Specifically, the chapter uncovers three
             empirically supported theses. A functional thesis, according
             to which our memory system not only processes information
             about past events but also uses this information to
             construct useful anticipations of possible future events. A
             computational thesis, according to which statistical
             regularities, along with individual limitations and goals,
             probabilistically constrain the search space examined during
             memory retrieval. And a metaphysical thesis, according to
             which memories do not exist as subpersonal-level brain
             structures encoding particular intentional contents but
             rather as personal-level psychological phenomena only
             accessible from the intentional stance.},
   Doi = {10.1093/oso/9780199367511.003.0005},
   Key = {fds337053}
}

@article{fds335562,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Memory, attention, and joint reminiscing},
   Pages = {200-220},
   Booktitle = {New Directions in the Philosophy of Memory},
   Publisher = {Routledge},
   Year = {2018},
   Month = {January},
   ISBN = {9781138065604},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9781315159591},
   Abstract = {When people jointly reminisce, they often talk about past
             objects, which may or may no longer exist. How can two or
             more people jointly refer to an object that is long gone-or
             at least, that is not present in their surrounding? In this
             chapter, I offer a three-part answer to this question.
             First, I suggest that our capacity to remember intentional
             objects during memory retrieval depends on our capacity to
             direct our attention inwardly toward the relevant component
             of a memorial content-a mental act I call mental ostension.
             Second, I argue that, for us to refer to remembered
             intentional objects, we must possess the ability to refer to
             them indirectly or “deferredly” by way of mentally
             ostending toward a present mental content; in short, we must
             be capable of deferred mental ostension. Finally, I claim
             that to jointly reminisce, we must have the capacity to
             guide someone else’s attention inwardly toward the
             relevant aspect of the mental content we want them to focus
             on so that they become aware of the past object we are
             deferredly ostending; that is, we need concerted deferred
             mental ostension.},
   Doi = {10.4324/9781315159591},
   Key = {fds335562}
}

@article{fds335563,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Gessell, B},
   Title = {Why episodic memory may not be for communication.},
   Journal = {The Behavioral and brain sciences},
   Volume = {41},
   Pages = {e8},
   Publisher = {Cambridge University Press (CUP)},
   Year = {2018},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0140525x17001303},
   Abstract = {Three serious challenges to Mahr & Csibra's (M&C's) proposal
             are presented. First, we argue that the epistemic attitude
             that they claim is unique to remembering also applies to
             some forms of imaginative simulations that aren't memories.
             Second, we argue that their account cannot accommodate
             critical neuropsychological evidence. Finally, we argue that
             their proposal looks unconvincing when compared to more
             parsimonious evolutionary accounts.},
   Doi = {10.1017/s0140525x17001303},
   Key = {fds335563}
}

@article{fds340469,
   Author = {Gessell, B and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {The discontinuity of levels in cognitive
             science},
   Journal = {Teorema},
   Volume = {37},
   Number = {3},
   Pages = {151-165},
   Year = {2018},
   Month = {January},
   Abstract = {We begin by characterizing Dennett’s “homuncular
             functionalist” view of the mind, as described in his early
             work. We then contrast that view with the one outlined in
             From Bacteria to Bach and Back. We argue that recent changes
             in Dennett’s view have produced tension in the way he
             conceives of functional decompositions. Functional
             decompositions based on the intentional stance are supposed
             to reach a bottom, “dumb” level which can be explained
             mechanically; however, since Dennett now believes that
             neurons may need to be described intentionally, it is not
             clear whether our explanations of cognitive functions can
             ever align with our explanations of neuronal and network
             behaviors. We explore the consequences of this tension for
             Dennett’s view, and for cognitive neuroscience in
             general.},
   Key = {fds340469}
}

@article{fds329948,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Parikh, N and Stewart, GW and Szpunar, KK and Schacter, DL},
   Title = {Neural activity associated with repetitive simulation of
             episodic counterfactual thoughts.},
   Journal = {Neuropsychologia},
   Volume = {106},
   Pages = {123-132},
   Year = {2017},
   Month = {November},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2017.09.022},
   Abstract = {When people revisit past autobiographical events they often
             imagine alternative ways in which such events could have
             occurred. Often these episodic counterfactual thoughts
             (eCFT) are momentary and fleeting, but sometimes they are
             simulated frequently and repeatedly. However, little is
             known about the neural differences between frequently versus
             infrequently repeated eCFT. The current study explores this
             issue. In a three-session study, participants were asked to
             simulate alternative ways positive, negative, and neutral
             autobiographical memories could have occurred. Half of these
             eCFT were repeatedly re-simulated while the other half were
             not. Immediately after, participants were asked to simulate
             all these eCFT again while undergoing fMRI. A partial least
             squares analysis on the resultant fMRI data revealed that
             eCFT that were not frequently repeated preferentially
             engaged brain regions including middle (BA 21) and superior
             temporal gyri (BA 38/39), middle (BA 11) and superior
             frontal gyri (BA 9), and hippocampus. By contrast,
             frequently repeated eCFT preferentially engaged regions
             including medial frontal gyri (BA 10), anterior cingulate
             cortex, insula, and inferior parietal lobule (BA 40). Direct
             contrasts for each type of eCFT were also conducted. The
             results of these analyses suggest differential contributions
             of regions traditionally associated with eCFT, such as BA
             10, anterior cingulate cortex, and hippocampus, as a
             function of kind of eCFT and frequency of repetition.
             Consequences for future research on eCFT and rumination are
             considered.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2017.09.022},
   Key = {fds329948}
}

@article{fds329949,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Memory and imagination},
   Pages = {127-140},
   Booktitle = {The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Memory},
   Publisher = {Routledge},
   Year = {2017},
   Month = {June},
   ISBN = {9781138909366},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9781315687315},
   Doi = {10.4324/9781315687315},
   Key = {fds329949}
}

@article{fds326194,
   Author = {Stanley, ML and Henne, P and Iyengar, V and Sinnott-Armstrong, W and De
             Brigard, F},
   Title = {I'm not the person I used to be: The self and
             autobiographical memories of immoral actions.},
   Journal = {Journal of experimental psychology. General},
   Volume = {146},
   Number = {6},
   Pages = {884-895},
   Year = {2017},
   Month = {June},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/xge0000317},
   Abstract = {People maintain a positive identity in at least two ways:
             They evaluate themselves more favorably than other people,
             and they judge themselves to be better now than they were in
             the past. Both strategies rely on autobiographical memories.
             The authors investigate the role of autobiographical
             memories of lying and emotional harm in maintaining a
             positive identity. For memories of lying to or emotionally
             harming others, participants judge their own actions as less
             morally wrong and less negative than those in which other
             people lied to or emotionally harmed them. Furthermore,
             people judge those actions that happened further in the past
             to be more morally wrong than those that happened more
             recently. Finally, for periods of the past when they
             believed that they were very different people than they are
             now, participants judge their actions to be more morally
             wrong and more negative than those actions from periods of
             their pasts when they believed that they were very similar
             to who they are now. The authors discuss these findings in
             relation to theories about the function of autobiographical
             memory and moral cognition in constructing and perceiving
             the self over time. (PsycINFO Database Record},
   Doi = {10.1037/xge0000317},
   Key = {fds326194}
}

@article{fds327002,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Cognitive systems and the changing brain},
   Journal = {Philosophical Explorations},
   Volume = {20},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {224-241},
   Publisher = {Informa UK Limited},
   Year = {2017},
   Month = {May},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13869795.2017.1312503},
   Abstract = {The notion of cognitive system is widely used in
             explanations in cognitive psychology and neuroscience.
             Traditional approaches define cognitive systems in an
             agent-relative way, that is, via top-down functional
             decomposition that assumes a cognitive agent as starting
             point. The extended cognition movement challenged that
             approach by questioning the primacy of the notion of
             cognitive agent. In response, [Adams, F., and K. Aizawa.
             2001. The Bounds of Cognition. Oxford, UK: Wiley-Blackwell.]
             suggested that to have a clear understanding of what a
             cognitive system is we may need to solve “the demarcation
             challenge”: the problem of identifying a reliable way to
             determine which mechanisms that are causally responsible for
             the production of a certain cognitive process constitute a
             cognitive system responsible for such process and which ones
             do not. Recently, [Rupert, R. 2009. Cognitive Systems and
             the Extended Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.] offered
             a solution based on the idea that the mechanisms that
             constitute a cognitive system are integrated in a particular
             sense. In this paper I critically review Rupert’s solution
             and argue against it. Additionally, I argue that a
             successful account of cognitive system must accommodate the
             fact that the neural mechanisms causally responsible for the
             production of a cognitive process are diachronically dynamic
             and yet functionally stable. At the end, I offer a
             suggestion as to how to accommodate this diachronic
             dynamicity without losing functional stability. I conclude
             by drawing some implications for the discussion on cognitive
             ontologies.},
   Doi = {10.1080/13869795.2017.1312503},
   Key = {fds327002}
}

@article{fds342710,
   Author = {Stanley, ML and Stewart, GW and Brigard, FD},
   Title = {Counterfactual Plausibility and Comparative
             Similarity.},
   Journal = {Cognitive science},
   Volume = {41 Suppl 5},
   Pages = {1216-1228},
   Year = {2017},
   Month = {May},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12451},
   Abstract = {Counterfactual thinking involves imagining hypothetical
             alternatives to reality. Philosopher David Lewis (1973,
             1979) argued that people estimate the subjective
             plausibility that a counterfactual event might have occurred
             by comparing an imagined possible world in which the
             counterfactual statement is true against the current, actual
             world in which the counterfactual statement is false.
             Accordingly, counterfactuals considered to be true in
             possible worlds comparatively more similar to ours are
             judged as more plausible than counterfactuals deemed true in
             possible worlds comparatively less similar. Although Lewis
             did not originally develop his notion of comparative
             similarity to be investigated as a psychological construct,
             this study builds upon his idea to empirically investigate
             comparative similarity as a possible psychological strategy
             for evaluating the perceived plausibility of counterfactual
             events. More specifically, we evaluate judgments of
             comparative similarity between episodic memories and
             episodic counterfactual events as a factor influencing
             people's judgments of plausibility in counterfactual
             simulations, and we also compare it against other factors
             thought to influence judgments of counterfactual
             plausibility, such as ease of simulation and prior
             simulation. Our results suggest that the greater the
             perceived similarity between the original memory and the
             episodic counterfactual event, the greater the perceived
             plausibility that the counterfactual event might have
             occurred. While similarity between actual and counterfactual
             events, ease of imagining, and prior simulation of the
             counterfactual event were all significantly related to
             counterfactual plausibility, comparative similarity best
             captured the variance in ratings of counterfactual
             plausibility. Implications for existing theories on the
             determinants of counterfactual plausibility are
             discussed.},
   Doi = {10.1111/cogs.12451},
   Key = {fds342710}
}

@article{fds327003,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Rodriguez, DC and Montañés,
             P},
   Title = {Exploring the experience of episodic past, future, and
             counterfactual thinking in younger and older adults: A study
             of a Colombian sample.},
   Journal = {Consciousness and cognition},
   Volume = {51},
   Pages = {258-267},
   Year = {2017},
   Month = {May},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2017.04.007},
   Abstract = {Although extant evidence suggests that many neural and
             cognitive mechanisms underlying episodic past, future, and
             counterfactual thinking overlap, recent results have
             uncovered differences among these three processes. However,
             the extent to which there may be age-related differences in
             the phenomenological characteristics associated with
             episodic past, future and counterfactual thinking remains
             unclear. This study used adapted versions of the Memory
             Characteristics Questionnaire and the Autobiographical
             Interview in younger and older adults to investigate the
             subjective experience of episodic past, future and
             counterfactual thinking. The results suggest that, across
             all conditions, younger adults generated more internal
             details than older adults. However, older adults generated
             more external details for episodic future and counterfactual
             thinking than younger adults. Additionally, younger and
             older adults generated more internal details, and gave
             higher sensory and contextual ratings, for memories rather
             than future and counterfactual thoughts. Methodological and
             theoretical consequences for extant theories of mental
             simulation are discussed.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.concog.2017.04.007},
   Key = {fds327003}
}

@article{fds318357,
   Author = {Henne, P and Pinillos, Á and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Cause by Omission and Norm: Not Watering
             Plants},
   Journal = {Australasian Journal of Philosophy},
   Volume = {95},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {270-283},
   Publisher = {Informa UK Limited},
   Year = {2017},
   Month = {April},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2016.1182567},
   Abstract = {People generally accept that there is causation by
             omission—that the omission of some events cause some
             related events. But this acceptance elicits the selection
             problem, or the difficulty of explaining the selection of a
             particular omissive cause or class of causes from the causal
             conditions. Some theorists contend that dependence theories
             of causation cannot resolve this problem. In this paper, we
             argue that the appeal to norms adequately resolves the
             selection problem for dependence theories, and we provide
             novel experimental evidence for it.},
   Doi = {10.1080/00048402.2016.1182567},
   Key = {fds318357}
}

@article{fds323231,
   Author = {Stanley, ML and Parikh, N and Stewart, GW and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Emotional intensity in episodic autobiographical memory and
             counterfactual thinking.},
   Journal = {Consciousness and cognition},
   Volume = {48},
   Pages = {283-291},
   Year = {2017},
   Month = {February},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2016.12.013},
   Abstract = {Episodic counterfactual thoughts-imagined alternative ways
             in which personal past events might have occurred-are
             frequently accompanied by intense emotions. Here,
             participants recollected positive and negative
             autobiographical memories and then generated better and
             worse episodic counterfactual events from those memories.
             Our results suggest that the projected emotional intensity
             during the simulated remembered/imagined event is
             significantly higher than but typically positively related
             to the emotional intensity while remembering/imagining the
             event. Furthermore, repeatedly simulating counterfactual
             events heightened the emotional intensity felt while
             simulating the counterfactual event. Finally, for both the
             emotional intensity accompanying the experience of
             remembering/imagining and the projected emotional intensity
             during the simulated remembered/imagined event, the
             emotional intensity of negative memories was greater than
             the emotional intensity of upward counterfactuals generated
             from them but lower than the emotional intensity of downward
             counterfactuals generated from them. These findings are
             discussed in relation to clinical work and functional
             theories of counterfactual thinking.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.concog.2016.12.013},
   Key = {fds323231}
}

@article{fds323662,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Brady, TF and Ruzic, L and Schacter,
             DL},
   Title = {Tracking the emergence of memories: A category-learning
             paradigm to explore schema-driven recognition.},
   Journal = {Memory & cognition},
   Volume = {45},
   Number = {1},
   Pages = {105-120},
   Year = {2017},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.3758/s13421-016-0643-6},
   Abstract = {Previous research has shown that prior knowledge structures
             or schemas affect recognition memory. However, since the
             acquisition of schemas occurs over prolonged periods of
             time, few paradigms allow the direct manipulation of schema
             acquisition to study their effect on memory performance.
             Recently, a number of parallelisms in recognition memory
             between studies involving schemas and studies involving
             category learning have been identified. The current paper
             capitalizes on these findings and offers a novel
             experimental paradigm that allows manipulation of category
             learning between individuals to study the effects of schema
             acquisition on recognition. First, participants learn to
             categorize computer-generated items whose category-inclusion
             criteria differ between participants. Next, participants
             study items that belong to either the learned category, the
             non-learned category, both, or neither. Finally,
             participants receive a recognition test that includes old
             and new items, either from the learned, the non-learned, or
             neither category. Using variations on this paradigm, four
             experiments were conducted. The results from the first three
             studies suggest that learning a category increases hit rates
             for old category-consistent items and false alarm rates for
             new category-consistent lures. Absent the category learning,
             no such effects are evident, even when participants are
             exposed to the same learning trials as those who learned the
             categories. The results from the fourth experiment suggest
             that, at least for false alarm rates, the effects of
             category learning are not solely attributable to frequency
             of occurrence of category-consistent items during learning.
             Implications for recognition memory as well as advantages of
             the proposed paradigm are discussed.},
   Doi = {10.3758/s13421-016-0643-6},
   Key = {fds323662}
}

@article{fds359515,
   Author = {Brigard, FD},
   Title = {The problem of consciousness for philosophy of mind and of
             psychiatry},
   Journal = {Ideas y Valores},
   Volume = {66},
   Pages = {15-45},
   Year = {2017},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.15446/ideasyvalores.v66n3Supl.65652},
   Abstract = {Psychiatrists often encounter patients whose symptoms
             include disorders or impairments of consciousness.
             Unfortunately, the meaning of the term consciousness is not
             altogether clear. This article presents a systematic review
             of various meanings attributed to this term, as well as of
             diverse associated philosophical problems. Likewise, it
             reconstructs some philosophical and scientific theories of
             consciousness, identifying their advantages and
             disadvantages. Finally, it offers some suggestions for the
             use of the term consciousness in psychiatry.},
   Doi = {10.15446/ideasyvalores.v66n3Supl.65652},
   Key = {fds359515}
}

@article{fds331533,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Responsibility and the relevance of alternative future
             possibilities},
   Journal = {Teoria},
   Volume = {37},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {25-35},
   Year = {2017},
   Month = {January},
   Abstract = {In the past decade, philosophical and psychological research
             on people's beliefs about free will and responsibility has
             skyrocketed. For the most part, these vignette-based studies
             have exclusively focused on participants' judgments of the
             causal history of the events leading up to an agent's action
             and considerations about what the agent could have done
             differently in the past. However, recent evidence suggests
             that, when judging whether or not an individual is
             responsible for a certain action - even in concrete,
             emotionally laden and fully deterministic scenarios -
             considerations about alternative future possibilities may
             become relevant. This paper reviews this evidence and
             suggests a way of interpreting the nature of these effects
             as well as some consequences for experimental philosophy and
             psychology of free will and responsibility going
             forward.},
   Key = {fds331533}
}

@article{fds320134,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Giovanello, KS and Stewart, GW and Lockrow, AW and O'Brien, MM and Spreng, RN},
   Title = {Characterizing the subjective experience of episodic past,
             future, and counterfactual thinking in healthy younger and
             older adults.},
   Journal = {Quarterly journal of experimental psychology
             (2006)},
   Volume = {69},
   Number = {12},
   Pages = {2358-2375},
   Year = {2016},
   Month = {December},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17470218.2015.1115529},
   Abstract = {Recent evidence demonstrates remarkable overlap in the
             neural and cognitive mechanisms underlying episodic memory,
             episodic future thinking, and episodic counterfactual
             thinking. However, the extent to which the phenomenological
             characteristics associated with these mental simulations
             change as a result of ageing remains largely unexplored. The
             current study employs adapted versions of the Memory
             Characteristics Questionnaire and the Autobiographical
             Interview to compare the phenomenological characteristics
             associated with both positive and negative episodic past,
             future, and counterfactual simulations in younger and older
             adults. Additionally, it explores the influence of perceived
             likelihood in the experience of such simulations. The
             results indicate that, across all simulations, older adults
             generate more external details and report higher ratings of
             vividness, composition, and intensity than young adults.
             Conversely, younger adults generate more internal details
             across all conditions and rated positive and negative likely
             future events as more likely than did older adults.
             Additionally, both younger and older adults reported higher
             ratings for sensory, composition, and intensity factors
             during episodic memories relative to future and
             counterfactual thoughts. Finally, for both groups, ratings
             of spatial coherence and composition were higher for likely
             counterfactuals than for both unlikely counterfactuals and
             future simulations. Implications for the psychology of
             mental simulation and ageing are discussed.},
   Doi = {10.1080/17470218.2015.1115529},
   Key = {fds320134}
}

@article{fds325468,
   Author = {Henne, P and Chituc, V and De Brigard and F and Sinnott-Armstrong,
             W},
   Title = {An Empirical Refutation of 'Ought' Implies
             'Can'},
   Journal = {Analysis (United Kingdom)},
   Volume = {76},
   Number = {3},
   Pages = {283-290},
   Publisher = {Oxford University Press (OUP)},
   Year = {2016},
   Month = {July},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/analys/anw041},
   Doi = {10.1093/analys/anw041},
   Key = {fds325468}
}

@article{fds318358,
   Author = {Chituc, V and Henne, P and Sinnott-Armstrong, W and De Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Blame, not ability, impacts moral "ought" judgments for
             impossible actions: Toward an empirical refutation of
             "ought" implies "can".},
   Journal = {Cognition},
   Volume = {150},
   Pages = {20-25},
   Year = {2016},
   Month = {May},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2016.01.013},
   Abstract = {Recently, psychologists have explored moral concepts
             including obligation, blame, and ability. While little
             empirical work has studied the relationships among these
             concepts, philosophers have widely assumed such a
             relationship in the principle that "ought" implies "can,"
             which states that if someone ought to do something, then
             they must be able to do it. The cognitive underpinnings of
             these concepts are tested in the three experiments reported
             here. In Experiment 1, most participants judge that an agent
             ought to keep a promise that he is unable to keep, but only
             when he is to blame for the inability. Experiment 2 shows
             that such "ought" judgments correlate with judgments of
             blame, rather than with judgments of the agent's ability.
             Experiment 3 replicates these findings for moral "ought"
             judgments and finds that they do not hold for nonmoral
             "ought" judgments, such as what someone ought to do to
             fulfill their desires. These results together show that folk
             moral judgments do not conform to a widely assumed
             philosophical principle that "ought" implies "can." Instead,
             judgments of blame play a modulatory role in some judgments
             of obligation.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.cognition.2016.01.013},
   Key = {fds318358}
}

@article{fds347942,
   Author = {Stanley, ML and Brigard, FD},
   Title = {Modularity in network neuroscience and neural
             reuse.},
   Journal = {The Behavioral and brain sciences},
   Volume = {39},
   Pages = {e133},
   Year = {2016},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0140525x15001673},
   Abstract = {Neural reuse allegedly stands in stark contrast against a
             modular view of the brain. However, the development of
             unique modularity algorithms in network science has provided
             the means to identify functionally cooperating, specialized
             subsystems in a way that remains consistent with the neural
             reuse view and offers a set of rigorous tools to fully
             engage in Anderson's (2014) research program.},
   Doi = {10.1017/s0140525x15001673},
   Key = {fds347942}
}

@article{fds341031,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Consciousness and moral responsibility},
   Journal = {Analysis (United Kingdom)},
   Volume = {75},
   Number = {4},
   Pages = {661-667},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {October},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/analys/anv012},
   Doi = {10.1093/analys/anv012},
   Key = {fds341031}
}

@article{fds320135,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Nathan Spreng and R and Mitchell, JP and Schacter,
             DL},
   Title = {Neural activity associated with self, other, and
             object-based counterfactual thinking.},
   Journal = {NeuroImage},
   Volume = {109},
   Pages = {12-26},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {April},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.neuroimage.2014.12.075},
   Abstract = {Previous research has shown that autobiographical episodic
             counterfactual thinking-i.e., mental simulations about
             alternative ways in which one's life experiences could have
             occurred-engages the brain's default network (DN). However,
             it remains unknown whether or not the DN is also engaged
             during impersonal counterfactual thoughts, specifically
             those involving other people or objects. The current study
             compares brain activity during counterfactual simulations
             involving the self, others and objects. In addition,
             counterfactual thoughts involving others were manipulated in
             terms of similarity and familiarity with the simulated
             characters. The results indicate greater involvement of DN
             during person-based (i.e., self and other) as opposed to
             object-based counterfactual simulations. However, the
             involvement of different regions of the DN during
             other-based counterfactual simulations was modulated by how
             close and/or similar the simulated character was perceived
             to be by the participant. Simulations involving unfamiliar
             characters preferentially recruited dorsomedial prefrontal
             cortex. Simulations involving unfamiliar similar characters,
             characters with whom participants identified personality
             traits, recruited lateral temporal gyrus. Finally, our
             results also revealed differential coupling of right
             hippocampus with lateral prefrontal and temporal cortex
             during counterfactual simulations involving familiar similar
             others, but with left transverse temporal gyrus and medial
             frontal and inferior temporal gyri during counterfactual
             simulations involving either oneself or unfamiliar
             dissimilar others. These results suggest that different
             brain mechanisms are involved in the simulation of personal
             and impersonal counterfactual thoughts, and that the extent
             to which regions associated with autobiographical memory are
             recruited during the simulation of counterfactuals involving
             others depends on the perceived similarity and familiarity
             with the simulated individuals.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.neuroimage.2014.12.075},
   Key = {fds320135}
}

@article{fds347943,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Book review: Involuntary autobiographical memories: An
             introduction to the unbidden past},
   Journal = {Memory Studies},
   Volume = {8},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {255-257},
   Publisher = {SAGE Publications},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {April},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/1750698014534786},
   Doi = {10.1177/1750698014534786},
   Key = {fds347943}
}

@misc{fds305550,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Finding Memory: Interview with Daniel L.
             Schacter},
   Journal = {Universitas Psychologica},
   Volume = {12},
   Number = {5},
   Pages = {2605-1610},
   Publisher = {Pontificia Universidad Javeriana},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {January},
   ISSN = {2011-2777},
   Key = {fds305550}
}

@article{fds305551,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Eliminando el fantasma de la máquina. Del alma al software
             1},
   Journal = {Revista Colombiana de Psiquiatría},
   Volume = {32},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {175-192},
   Publisher = {Asociacion Colombiana de Psiquiatria},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {January},
   ISSN = {0034-7450},
   Key = {fds305551}
}

@article{fds305552,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {El advenimiento de la metáfora mente-computador. Del alma
             al software 3},
   Journal = {Revista Colombiana de Psiquiatría},
   Volume = {33},
   Number = {1},
   Pages = {64-85},
   Publisher = {Asociacion Colombiana de Psiquiatria},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {January},
   ISSN = {0034-7450},
   Key = {fds305552}
}

@article{fds305553,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Capas limítrofes y dominios de evidencia en ciencia
             cognitiva},
   Journal = {Universitas Philosophica},
   Volume = {45},
   Pages = {53-77},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {January},
   ISSN = {0120-5323},
   url = {http://people.duke.edu/~fd13/De_Brigard_2006_UnivPhil.pdf},
   Key = {fds305553}
}

@article{fds305555,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Attention, Consciousness, and Commonsense},
   Journal = {Journal of Consciousness Studies: controversies in science
             and the humanities},
   Volume = {17},
   Number = {9/10},
   Pages = {189-201},
   Publisher = {Imprint Academic},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {January},
   ISSN = {1355-8250},
   Key = {fds305555}
}

@article{fds305556,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Memoria, neurociencia y educación},
   Pages = {179-194},
   Booktitle = {La pizarra de Babel: Puentes entre neurociencia, psicologia
             y educación},
   Publisher = {Libros del Zorzal},
   Editor = {Lipina, S and Sigman, M},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {January},
   Key = {fds305556}
}

@article{fds305557,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Review of “Attention is Cognitive Unison”. Christopher
             Mole. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).},
   Journal = {Journal of Consciousness Studies: controversies in science
             and the humanities},
   Volume = {20},
   Number = {1/2},
   Pages = {239-247},
   Publisher = {Imprint Academic},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {January},
   ISSN = {1355-8250},
   Key = {fds305557}
}

@article{fds305558,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {In defense of the self-stultification objection},
   Journal = {Journal of Consciousness Studies: controversies in science
             and the humanities},
   Volume = {21},
   Number = {5/6},
   Pages = {120-130},
   Publisher = {Imprint Academic},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {January},
   ISSN = {1355-8250},
   Key = {fds305558}
}

@article{fds287445,
   Author = {Schacter, DL and Benoit, RG and De Brigard and F and Szpunar,
             KK},
   Title = {Episodic future thinking and episodic counterfactual
             thinking: intersections between memory and
             decisions.},
   Journal = {Neurobiology of learning and memory},
   Volume = {117},
   Pages = {14-21},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {January},
   ISSN = {1074-7427},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.nlm.2013.12.008},
   Abstract = {This article considers two recent lines of research
             concerned with the construction of imagined or simulated
             events that can provide insight into the relationship
             between memory and decision making. One line of research
             concerns episodic future thinking, which involves simulating
             episodes that might occur in one's personal future, and the
             other concerns episodic counterfactual thinking, which
             involves simulating episodes that could have happened in
             one's personal past. We first review neuroimaging studies
             that have examined the neural underpinnings of episodic
             future thinking and episodic counterfactual thinking. We
             argue that these studies have revealed that the two forms of
             episodic simulation engage a common core network including
             medial parietal, prefrontal, and temporal regions that also
             supports episodic memory. We also note that neuroimaging
             studies have documented neural differences between episodic
             future thinking and episodic counterfactual thinking,
             including differences in hippocampal responses. We next
             consider behavioral studies that have delineated both
             similarities and differences between the two kinds of
             episodic simulation. The evidence indicates that episodic
             future and counterfactual thinking are characterized by
             similarly reduced levels of specific detail compared with
             episodic memory, but that the effects of repeatedly
             imagining a possible experience have sharply contrasting
             effects on the perceived plausibility of those events during
             episodic future thinking versus episodic counterfactual
             thinking. Finally, we conclude by discussing the functional
             consequences of future and counterfactual simulations for
             decisions.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.nlm.2013.12.008},
   Key = {fds287445}
}

@book{fds320136,
   Author = {Muñoz-Suárez, C and de Brigard, F and Daniel,
             D},
   Title = {Content and consciousness revisited},
   Pages = {1-220},
   Publisher = {Springer International Publishing},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {January},
   ISBN = {9783319173733},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-17374-0},
   Abstract = {What are the grounds for the distinction between the mental
             and the physical? What is it the relation between ascribing
             mental states to an organism and understanding its behavior?
             Are animals and complex systems vehicles of inner
             evolutionary environments? Is there a difference between
             personal and sub-personal level processes in the brain?
             Answers to these and other questions were developed in
             Daniel Dennett’s first book, Content and Consciousness
             (1969), where he sketched a unified theoretical framework
             for views that are now considered foundational in cognitive
             science and philosophy of mind. Content and Consciousness
             Revisited is devoted to reconsider the ideas and ideals
             introduced in Dennett’s seminal book, by covering its
             fundamental concepts, hypotheses and approaches and taking
             into account the findings and progress which have taken
             place during more than four decades. This book includes
             original and critical contributions about the relations
             between science and philosophy, the personal/sub-personal
             level distinction, intelligence, learning, intentionality,
             rationality, propositional attitudes, among other issues of
             scientific and philosophical interest. Each chapter embraces
             an updated approach to several disciplines, like cognitive
             science, cognitive psychology, philosophy of mind and
             cognitive psychiatry.},
   Doi = {10.1007/978-3-319-17374-0},
   Key = {fds320136}
}

@article{fds318359,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Hanna, E},
   Title = {Clinical applications of counterfactual thinking during
             memory reactivation.},
   Journal = {The Behavioral and brain sciences},
   Volume = {38},
   Pages = {e5},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0140525x14000351},
   Abstract = {The Integrative Memory Model offers a strong foundation upon
             which to build successful strategies for clinical
             intervention. The next challenge is to figure out which
             cognitive strategies are more likely to bring about
             successful and beneficial modifications of reactivated
             memories during therapy. In this commentary we suggest that
             exercising emotional regulation during episodic
             counterfactual thinking is likely to be a successful
             therapeutic strategy to bring about beneficial memory
             modifications.},
   Doi = {10.1017/s0140525x14000351},
   Key = {fds318359}
}

@article{fds320137,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {In defence of the self-stultification objection},
   Journal = {Journal of Consciousness Studies},
   Volume = {21},
   Number = {5-6},
   Pages = {120-130},
   Year = {2014},
   Month = {May},
   Abstract = {Epiphenomenalism holds that mental events are caused by
             physical events while not causing any physical effects
             whatsoever. The self-stultification objection is a venerable
             argument against epiphenomenalism according to which, if
             epiphenomenalism were true, we would not have knowledge of
             our own sensations. For the past three decades, W.S.
             Robinson has called into question the soundness of this
             objection, offering several arguments against it. Many of
             his arguments attempt to shift the burden of proof onto the
             opponents of epiphenomenalism, hoping to show that
             epiphenomenalism is no less stultifying than its contenders,
             such as dualism, functionalism, or identity theory. In the
             current paper I attempt to shift the burden of proof back to
             Robinson, and thus to defend the self-stultification
             objection, by offering two counterarguments against one of
             Robinson's objections to one of the key premises of the
             self-stultification objection.},
   Key = {fds320137}
}

@article{fds287446,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {The nature of memory traces},
   Journal = {Philosophy Compass},
   Volume = {9},
   Number = {6},
   Pages = {402-414},
   Publisher = {WILEY},
   Year = {2014},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12133},
   Abstract = {Memory trace was originally a philosophical term used to
             explain the phenomenon of remembering. Once debated by
             Plato, Aristotle, and Zeno of Citium, the notion seems more
             recently to have become the exclusive province of cognitive
             psychologists and neuroscientists. Nonetheless, this modern
             appropriation should not deter philosophers from thinking
             carefully about the nature of memory traces. On the
             contrary, scientific research on the nature of memory traces
             can rekindle philosopher's interest on this notion. With
             that general aim in mind, the present paper has three
             specific goals. First, it attempts to chart the most
             relevant philosophical views on the nature of memory traces
             from both a thematic and historical perspective. Second, it
             reviews critical findings in the psychology and the
             neuroscience of memory traces. Finally, it explains how such
             results lend support to or discredit specific philosophical
             positions on the nature of memory traces. This paper also
             touches upon the issues raised by recent empirical research
             that theories of memory traces need to accommodate in order
             to succeed. © 2014 The Author(s) Philosophy Compass © 2014
             John Wiley & Sons Ltd.},
   Doi = {10.1111/phc3.12133},
   Key = {fds287446}
}

@article{fds287451,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Is memory for remembering? Recollection as a form of
             episodic hypothetical thinking},
   Journal = {Synthese},
   Volume = {191},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {155-185},
   Publisher = {Springer Nature},
   Year = {2014},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://people.duke.edu/~fd13/De_Brigard_2013_Synthese.pdf},
   Abstract = {Misremembering is a systematic and ordinary occurrence in
             our daily lives. Since it is commonly assumed that the
             function of memory is to remember the past, misremembering
             is typically thought to happen because our memory system
             malfunctions. In this paper I argue that not all cases of
             misremembering are due to failures in our memory system. In
             particular, I argue that many ordinary cases of
             misremembering should not be seen as instances of memory's
             malfunction, but rather as the normal result of a larger
             cognitive system that performs a different function, and for
             which remembering is just one operation. Building upon
             extant psychological and neuroscientific evidence, I offer a
             picture of memory as an integral part of a larger system
             that supports not only thinking of what was the case and
             what potentially could be the case, but also what could have
             been the case. More precisely, I claim that remembering is a
             particular operation of a cognitive system that permits the
             flexible recombination of different components of encoded
             traces into representations of possible past events that
             might or might not have occurred, in the service of
             constructing mental simulations of possible future events.
             So that imagination and memory are but one thing, which for
             diverse considerations hath diverse names. Thomas Hobbes,
             Leviathan 1.2. © 2013 Springer Science+Business Media
             Dordrecht.},
   Doi = {10.1007/s11229-013-0247-7},
   Key = {fds287451}
}

@misc{fds287428,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {The New Paideia},
   Journal = {3:AM Magazine},
   Year = {2014},
   Key = {fds287428}
}

@misc{fds287429,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {The Anatomy of Amnesia},
   Journal = {Scientific American Mind},
   Pages = {33-37},
   Year = {2014},
   Key = {fds287429}
}

@article{fds287444,
   Author = {Banerjee, S and Cox, J and De Brigard and F and et. al.},
   Title = {The significance of cognitive neuroscience: Findings,
             applications and challenges},
   Pages = {1071-1078},
   Booktitle = {The Cognitive Neuroscience V},
   Publisher = {MIT Press},
   Address = {Cambridge, MA},
   Editor = {Mangum, R and Gazzaniga, M},
   Year = {2014},
   Key = {fds287444}
}

@article{fds287448,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Addis, DR and Ford, JH and Schacter, DL and Giovanello, KS},
   Title = {Remembering what could have happened: neural correlates of
             episodic counterfactual thinking.},
   Journal = {Neuropsychologia},
   Volume = {51},
   Number = {12},
   Pages = {2401-2414},
   Year = {2013},
   Month = {October},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2013.01.015},
   Abstract = {Recent evidence suggests that our capacities to remember the
             past and to imagine what might happen in the future largely
             depend on the same core brain network that includes the
             middle temporal lobe, the posterior cingulate/retrosplenial
             cortex, the inferior parietal lobe, the medial prefrontal
             cortex, and the lateral temporal cortex. However, the extent
             to which regions of this core brain network are also
             responsible for our capacity to think about what could have
             happened in our past, yet did not occur (i.e., episodic
             counterfactual thinking), is still unknown. The present
             study examined this issue. Using a variation of the
             experimental recombination paradigm (Addis, Pan, Vu, Laiser,
             & Schacter, 2009. Neuropsychologia. 47: 2222-2238),
             participants were asked both to remember personal past
             events and to envision alternative outcomes to such events
             while undergoing functional magnetic resonance imaging.
             Three sets of analyses were performed on the imaging data in
             order to investigate two related issues. First, a
             mean-centered spatiotemporal partial least square (PLS)
             analysis identified a pattern of brain activity across
             regions of the core network that was common to episodic
             memory and episodic counterfactual thinking. Second, a
             non-rotated PLS analysis identified two different patterns
             of brain activity for likely and unlikely episodic
             counterfactual thoughts, with the former showing significant
             overlap with the set of regions engaged during episodic
             recollection. Finally, a parametric modulation was conducted
             to explore the differential engagement of brain regions
             during counterfactual thinking, revealing that areas such as
             the parahippocampal gyrus and the right hippocampus were
             modulated by the subjective likelihood of counterfactual
             simulations. These results suggest that episodic
             counterfactual thinking engages regions that form the core
             brain network, and also that the subjective likelihood of
             our counterfactual thoughts modulates the engagement of
             different areas within this set of regions.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2013.01.015},
   Key = {fds287448}
}

@article{fds287450,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Szpunar, KK and Schacter, DL},
   Title = {Coming to grips with the past: effect of repeated simulation
             on the perceived plausibility of episodic counterfactual
             thoughts.},
   Journal = {Psychological science},
   Volume = {24},
   Number = {7},
   Pages = {1329-1334},
   Publisher = {SAGE Publications},
   Year = {2013},
   Month = {July},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0956797612468163},
   Abstract = {When people revisit previous experiences, they often engage
             in episodic counterfactual thinking: mental simulations of
             alternative ways in which personal past events could have
             occurred. The present study employed a novel experimental
             paradigm to examine the influence of repeated simulation on
             the perceived plausibility of upward, downward, and neutral
             episodic counterfactual thoughts. Participants were asked to
             remember negative, positive, and neutral autobiographical
             memories. One week later, they self-generated upward,
             downward, and neutral counterfactual alternatives to those
             memories. The following day, they resimulated each of those
             counterfactuals either once or four times. The results
             indicate that repeated simulation of upward, downward, and
             neutral episodic counterfactual events decreases their
             perceived plausibility while increasing ratings of the ease,
             detail, and valence of the simulations. This finding
             suggests a difference between episodic counterfactual
             thoughts and other kinds of self-referential simulations.
             Possible implications of this finding for pathological and
             nonpathological anxiety are discussed.},
   Doi = {10.1177/0956797612468163},
   Key = {fds287450}
}

@article{fds287449,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Brady, WJ},
   Title = {The Effect of What We Think may Happen on our Judgments of
             Responsibility},
   Journal = {Review of Philosophy and Psychology},
   Volume = {4},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {259-269},
   Publisher = {Springer Nature},
   Year = {2013},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s13164-013-0133-8},
   Abstract = {Recent evidence suggests that if a deterministic description
             of the events leading up to a morally questionable action is
             couched in mechanistic, reductionistic, concrete and/or
             emotionally salient terms, people are more inclined toward
             compatibilism than when those descriptions use
             non-mechanistic, non-reductionistic, abstract and/or
             emotionally neutral terms. To explain these results, it has
             been suggested that descriptions of the first kind are
             processed by a concrete cognitive system, while those of the
             second kind are processed by an abstract cognitive system.
             The current paper reports the results of three studies
             exploring whether or not considerations about possible
             future consequences of holding an agent responsible at a
             present time affect people's judgments of responsibility.
             The results obtained suggest first that the concrete system
             does not produce compatibilist judgments of responsibility
             unconditionally, even when facing appropriately mechanistic,
             reductionistic, emotionally loaded and concretely worded
             deterministic scenarios. Second, these results suggest that
             considerations about possible future consequences for
             innocent third parties that may follow as a result of
             holding an agent responsible affect people's judgment as to
             whether or not the agent is responsible for what she did.
             Finally, it is proposed that these results compliment extant
             evidence on the so-called "Side-effect effect", as they
             suggest that emotional reactions toward possible future side
             effects influence people's judgment of responsibility. The
             impact of these results for philosophy and moral psychology
             is discussed. © 2013 Springer Science+Business Media
             Dordrecht.},
   Doi = {10.1007/s13164-013-0133-8},
   Key = {fds287449}
}

@article{fds320138,
   Author = {Acevedo-Triana, C and Fernando Cardenas and P and de Brigard,
             F},
   Title = {Finding memory: Interview with Daniel L.
             Schacter},
   Journal = {Universitas Psychologica},
   Volume = {12},
   Number = {5},
   Pages = {1605-1610},
   Publisher = {Editorial Pontificia Universidad Javeriana},
   Year = {2013},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.11144/Javeriana.UPSY12-5.fmid},
   Abstract = {The present interview offers an annotated dialogue with Dr.
             Daniel L. Schacter, in which we had the chance to learn
             about his findings, his current studies, in their
             implications for memory and cognition. Dr. Schacter is
             currently William R. Kenan, Jr. Professor of Psychology at
             Harvard University. With more than 40 years of professional
             experience in research on cognition, Dr. Schacter has
             published over 400 articles, many in top scientific
             journals, and some have been cited thousands of times. For
             his multiple theoretical and empirical contributions to the
             field of psychology, Dr. Schacter recently received the
             American Psychological Association's Award for Distinguished
             Scientific Contributions.},
   Doi = {10.11144/Javeriana.UPSY12-5.fmid},
   Key = {fds320138}
}

@article{fds347944,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Attention is Cognitive Unison: An Essay in Philosophical
             Psychology},
   Journal = {JOURNAL OF CONSCIOUSNESS STUDIES},
   Volume = {20},
   Number = {1-2},
   Pages = {239-247},
   Publisher = {IMPRINT ACADEMIC},
   Year = {2013},
   Month = {January},
   Key = {fds347944}
}

@article{fds221957,
   Author = {(5) Schacter, D.L. and Benoit, R. and De Brigard and F. and Szpunar,
             K.K},
   Title = {Episodic future thinking and episodic counterfactual
             thinking: Intersections between memory and
             decisions.},
   Journal = {Neurobiology of Learning and Memory},
   Year = {2013},
   Key = {fds221957}
}

@article{fds287440,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Giovanello, KS and Kaufer, D},
   Title = {Neuroanatomy of Memory},
   Booktitle = {Behavioral Neurology and Neuropsychiatry},
   Publisher = {Cambridge University Press (CUP)},
   Editor = {Arcinegas, DB and Anderson, CA and Filley, CM},
   Year = {2013},
   Key = {fds287440}
}

@article{fds287442,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {What was I thinking? Dennett’s Content and Consciousness
             and the reality of propositional attitudes},
   Booktitle = {Content and Consciousness Revisited},
   Publisher = {Springer},
   Editor = {Muñoz-Suárez, CM and De Brigard and F},
   Year = {2013},
   Key = {fds287442}
}

@article{fds287443,
   Author = {St Jacques and P and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Neural correlates of autobiographical memory: Methodological
             Considerations.},
   Booktitle = {The Handbook on the Cognitive Neuroscience of
             Memory.},
   Publisher = {Wiley-Blackwell},
   Editor = {Durte, A and Barense, M and Addis, D},
   Year = {2013},
   Key = {fds287443}
}

@article{fds287447,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Review of “Involuntary Autobiographical Memories”.
             Dorthe Berntsen. (Cambridge University Press.
             2009)},
   Journal = {Memory Studies},
   Year = {2013},
   Key = {fds287447}
}

@article{fds287438,
   Author = {Giovanello, KS and De Brigard and F and Hennessey Ford and J and Kaufer,
             DI and Burke, JR and Browndyke, JN and Welsh-Bohmer,
             KA},
   Title = {Event-related functional magnetic resonance imaging changes
             during relational retrieval in normal aging and amnestic
             mild cognitive impairment.},
   Journal = {J Int Neuropsychol Soc},
   Volume = {18},
   Number = {5},
   Pages = {886-897},
   Year = {2012},
   Month = {September},
   ISSN = {1355-6177},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S1355617712000689},
   Abstract = {The earliest cognitive deficits observed in amnestic mild
             cognitive impairment (aMCI) appear to center on memory tasks
             that require relational memory (RM), the ability to link or
             integrate unrelated pieces of information. RM impairments in
             aMCI likely reflect neural changes in the medial temporal
             lobe (MTL) and posterior parietal cortex (PPC). We tested
             the hypothesis that individuals with aMCI, as compared to
             cognitively normal (CN) controls, would recruit neural
             regions outside of the MTL and PPC to support relational
             memory. To this end, we directly compared the neural
             underpinnings of successful relational retrieval in aMCI and
             CN groups, using event-related functional magnetic resonance
             imaging (fMRI), holding constant the stimuli and encoding
             task. The fMRI data showed that the CN, compared to the
             aMCI, group activated left precuneus, left angular gyrus,
             right posterior cingulate, and right parahippocampal cortex
             during relational retrieval, while the aMCI group, relative
             to the CN group, activated superior temporal gyrus and
             supramarginal gyrus for this comparison. Such findings
             indicate an early shift in the functional neural
             architecture of relational retrieval in aMCI, and may prove
             useful in future studies aimed at capitalizing on
             functionally intact neural regions as targets for treatment
             and slowing of the disease course. (JINS, 2012, 18,
             1-12).},
   Doi = {10.1017/S1355617712000689},
   Key = {fds287438}
}

@article{fds287439,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Giovanello, KS},
   Title = {Influence of outcome valence in the subjective experience of
             episodic past, future, and counterfactual
             thinking.},
   Journal = {Consciousness and cognition},
   Volume = {21},
   Number = {3},
   Pages = {1085-1096},
   Year = {2012},
   Month = {September},
   ISSN = {1053-8100},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2012.06.007},
   Abstract = {Recent findings suggest that our capacity to imagine the
             future depends on our capacity to remember the past.
             However, the extent to which episodic memory is involved in
             our capacity to think about what could have happened in our
             past, yet did not occur (i.e., episodic counterfactual
             thinking), remains largely unexplored. The current
             experiments investigate the phenomenological characteristics
             and the influence of outcome valence on the experience of
             past, future and counterfactual thoughts. Participants were
             asked to mentally simulate past, future, and counterfactual
             events with positive or negative outcomes. Features of their
             subjective experiences during each type of simulation were
             measured using questionnaires and autobiographical
             interviews. The results suggest that clarity and vividness
             were higher for past than future and counterfactual
             simulations. Additionally, emotional intensity was lower for
             counterfactual simulations than past and future simulations.
             Finally, outcome valence influenced participants' judgment
             of probability for future and counterfactual
             simulations.},
   Doi = {10.1016/j.concog.2012.06.007},
   Key = {fds287439}
}

@article{fds287436,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {The role of attention in conscious recollection.},
   Journal = {Frontiers in psychology},
   Volume = {3},
   Pages = {29},
   Publisher = {FRONTIERS MEDIA SA},
   Year = {2012},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00029},
   Abstract = {Most research on the relationship between attention and
             consciousness has been limited to perception. However,
             perceptions are not the only kinds of mental contents of
             which we can be conscious. An important set of conscious
             states that has not received proper treatment within this
             discussion is that of memories. This paper reviews
             compelling evidence indicating that attention may be
             necessary, but probably not sufficient, for conscious
             recollection. However, it is argued that unlike the case of
             conscious perception, the kind of attention required during
             recollection is internal, as opposed to external, attention.
             As such, the surveyed empirical evidence is interpreted as
             suggesting that internal attention is necessary, but
             probably not sufficient, for conscious recollection. The
             paper begins by justifying the need for clear distinctions
             among different kinds of attention, and then emphasizes the
             difference between internal and external attention. Next,
             evidence from behavioral, neuropsychological, and
             neuroimaging studies suggesting that internal attention is
             required for the successful retrieval of memorial contents
             is reviewed. In turn, it is argued that internal attention
             during recollection is what makes us conscious of the
             contents of retrieved memories; further evidence in support
             of this claim is also provided. Finally, it is suggested
             that internal attention is probably not sufficient for
             conscious recollection. Open questions and possible avenues
             for future research are also mentioned.},
   Doi = {10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00029},
   Key = {fds287436}
}

@article{fds287437,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Predictive memory and the surprising gap.},
   Journal = {Frontiers in psychology},
   Volume = {3},
   Pages = {420},
   Publisher = {FRONTIERS MEDIA SA},
   Year = {2012},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00420},
   Doi = {10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00420},
   Key = {fds287437}
}

@article{fds320139,
   Author = {de Brigard, F},
   Title = {Consciousness, attention and commonsense},
   Journal = {Journal of Consciousness Studies},
   Volume = {17},
   Number = {9-10},
   Pages = {189-201},
   Year = {2010},
   Month = {October},
   Abstract = {In a recent paper, Christopher Mole (2008) argued in favour
             of the view that, according to our commonsense psychology,
             while consciousness is necessary for attention, attention
             isn't necessary for consciousness. In this paper I offer an
             argument against this view. More precisely, I offer an
             argument against the claim that, according to our
             commonsense psychology, consciousness is necessary for
             attention. However, I don't claim it follows from this
             argument that commonsense has it the other way around, viz.
             that consciousness isn't necessary for attention. Instead, I
             want to motivate the claim that there isn't such a thing as
             the view of commonsense psychology about the relation
             between attention and consciousness. I argue that people's
             use of these terms - and, presumably, of their corresponding
             concepts - seems to be context dependent. I conclude with a
             discussion of the possible implications of this claim for
             the empirical study of attention and consciousness. ©
             Imprint Academic 2010.},
   Key = {fds320139}
}

@article{fds287435,
   Author = {Sarkissian, H and Chatterjee, A and De brigard, F and Knobe, J and Nichols, S and Sirker, S},
   Title = {Is belief in free will a cultural universal?},
   Journal = {Mind and Language},
   Volume = {25},
   Number = {3},
   Pages = {346-358},
   Publisher = {WILEY},
   Year = {2010},
   Month = {June},
   ISSN = {0268-1064},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0017.2010.01393.x},
   Abstract = {Recent experimental research has revealed surprising
             patterns in people's intuitions about free will and moral
             responsibility. One limitation of this research, however, is
             that it has been conducted exclusively on people from
             Western cultures. The present paper extends previous
             research by presenting a cross-cultural study examining
             intuitions about free will and moral responsibility in
             subjects from the United States, Hong Kong, India and
             Colombia. The results revealed a striking degree of
             cross-cultural convergence. In all four cultural groups, the
             majority of participants said that (a) our universe is
             indeterministic and (b) moral responsibility is not
             compatible with determinism. © 2010 Blackwell Publishing
             Ltd.},
   Doi = {10.1111/j.1468-0017.2010.01393.x},
   Key = {fds287435}
}

@article{fds305554,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {If you like it, does it matter if it’s
             real?},
   Journal = {Philosophical Psychology},
   Volume = {23},
   Number = {1},
   Pages = {43-57},
   Publisher = {Taylor & Francis (Routledge)},
   Year = {2010},
   Month = {February},
   ISSN = {1465-394X},
   url = {http://people.duke.edu/~fd13/De_Brigard_2010_PhilPsych.pdf},
   Abstract = {Most people's intuitive reaction after considering Nozick's
             experience machine thought-experiment seems to be just like
             his: we feel very little inclination to plug in to a virtual
             reality machine capable of providing us with pleasurable
             experiences. Many philosophers take this empirical fact as
             sufficient reason to believe that, more than pleasurable
             experiences, people care about "living in contact with
             reality." Such claim, however, assumes that people's
             reaction to the experience machine thought-experiment is due
             to the fact that they value reality over virtual
             experiences-an assumption that has seldom (if ever) been
             questioned. This paper challenges that very assumption. I
             report some experimental evidence suggesting that the
             intuition elicited by the thoughtexperiment may be
             explainable by the fact that people are averse to abandon
             the life they have been experiencing so far, regardless of
             whether such life is virtual or real. I use then an
             explanatory model, derived from what behavioral economists
             and psychologists call the status quo bias, to make sense of
             these results. Finally, I argue that since this explanation
             also accounts for people's reaction toward Nozick's
             thought-experiment, it would be wrong to take such intuition
             as evidence that people value being in touch with reality.
             © 2010 Taylor & Francis.},
   Doi = {10.1080/09515080903532290},
   Key = {fds305554}
}

@article{fds287434,
   Author = {De Brigard and F and Prinz, J},
   Title = {Attention and consciousness.},
   Journal = {Wiley interdisciplinary reviews. Cognitive
             science},
   Volume = {1},
   Number = {1},
   Pages = {51-59},
   Publisher = {WILEY},
   Year = {2010},
   Month = {January},
   ISSN = {1939-5078},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/wcs.27},
   Abstract = {For the past three decades there has been a substantial
             amount of scientific evidence supporting the view that
             attention is necessary and sufficient for perceptual
             representations to become conscious (i.e., for there to be
             something that it is like to experience a representational
             perceptual state). This view, however, has been recently
             questioned on the basis of some alleged counterevidence. In
             this paper we survey some of the most important recent
             findings. In doing so, we have two primary goals. The first
             is descriptive: we provide a literature review for those
             seeking an understanding of the present debate. The second
             is editorial: we suggest that the evidence alleging
             dissociations between consciousness and attention is not
             decisive. Thus, this is an opinionated overview of the
             debate. By presenting our assessment, we hope to bring out
             both sides in the debate and to underscore that the issues
             here remain matters of intense controversy and ongoing
             investigation. Copyright © 2009 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. For
             further resources related to this article, please visit the
             WIREs website.},
   Doi = {10.1002/wcs.27},
   Key = {fds287434}
}

@article{fds287433,
   Author = {de Brigard, F and Mandelbaum, E and Ripley, D},
   Title = {Responsibility and the brain sciences},
   Journal = {Ethical Theory and Moral Practice},
   Volume = {12},
   Number = {5},
   Pages = {511-524},
   Publisher = {Springer Nature},
   Year = {2009},
   Month = {November},
   ISSN = {1386-2820},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10677-008-9143-5},
   Abstract = {Some theorists think that the more we get to know about the
             neural underpinnings of our behaviors, the less likely we
             will be to hold people responsible for their actions. This
             intuition has driven some to suspect that as neuroscience
             gains insight into the neurological causes of our actions,
             people will cease to view others as morally responsible for
             their actions, thus creating a troubling quandary for our
             legal system. This paper provides empirical evidence against
             such intuitions. Particularly, our studies of folk
             intuitions suggest that (1) when the causes of an action are
             described in neurological terms, they are not found to be
             any more exculpatory than when described in psychological
             terms, and (2) agents are not held fully responsible even
             for actions that are fully neurologically caused. ©
             Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2008.},
   Doi = {10.1007/s10677-008-9143-5},
   Key = {fds287433}
}

@article{fds287431,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Review of The Origins of Meaning: Language in the Light of
             Evolution},
   Journal = {Philosophical Psychology},
   Volume = {22},
   Number = {4},
   Pages = {529-533},
   Publisher = {Informa UK Limited},
   Year = {2009},
   Month = {August},
   ISSN = {0951-5089},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09515080903157924},
   Doi = {10.1080/09515080903157924},
   Key = {fds287431}
}

@article{fds287432,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Comentario crítico a “Las dificultades del compatibilismo
             de Dennett”de José Antonio Guerrero del
             Amo},
   Journal = {Ideas y Valores: Revista Colombiana de Filosofía},
   Volume = {58},
   Number = {141},
   Pages = {262-268},
   Year = {2009},
   Key = {fds287432}
}

@misc{fds287427,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Estados Unidos: Entre ilusiones y prejuicios},
   Journal = {Revista Javeriana},
   Year = {2005},
   Key = {fds287427}
}

@article{fds287430,
   Author = {De Brigard and F},
   Title = {En busca de la mente cerebral. Del alma al software
             2},
   Journal = {Revista Colombiana de Psiquiatría},
   Volume = {32},
   Number = {4},
   Pages = {373-390},
   Publisher = {Asociacion Colombiana de Psiquiatria},
   Year = {2003},
   ISSN = {0034-7450},
   Key = {fds287430}
}

@book{fds287441,
   Author = {Montañés, P and De Brigard and F},
   Title = {Neuropsicologia clinica y cognoscitiva},
   Pages = {267 pages},
   Publisher = {Univ. Nacional de Colombia},
   Year = {2001},
   ISBN = {9789588063041},
   url = {http://www.bdigital.unal.edu.co/1511/},
   Key = {fds287441}
}


Duke University * Arts & Sciences * Philosophy * Faculty * Staff * Grad * Reload * Login