Publications of Evan Charney    :chronological  alphabetical  combined listing:

We've launched a new site so please go to People & Research for current information on our faculty and staff.

%% Journal Articles   
@article{fds321758,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Genes, behavior, and behavior genetics.},
   Journal = {Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews. Cognitive
             Science},
   Volume = {8},
   Number = {1-2},
   Year = {2017},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/wcs.1405},
   Abstract = {According to the 'first law' of behavior genetics, 'All
             human behavioral traits are heritable.' Accepting the
             validity of this first law and employing statistical
             methods, researchers within psychology, sociology, political
             science, economics, and business claim to have demonstrated
             that all the behaviors studied by their disciplines are
             heritable-no matter how culturally specific these behaviors
             appear to be. Further, in many cases they claim to have
             identified specific genes that play a role in those
             behaviors. The validity of behavior genetics as a discipline
             depends upon the validity of the research methods used to
             justify such claims. It also depends, foundationally, upon
             certain key assumptions concerning the relationship between
             genotype (one's specific DNA sequences) and phenotype (any
             and all observable traits or characteristics). In this
             article, I examine-and find serious flaws with-both the
             methodologies of behavior genetics and the underlying
             assumptions concerning the genotype-phenotype relationship.
             WIREs Cogn Sci 2017, 8:e1405. doi: 10.1002/wcs.1405 For
             further resources related to this article, please visit the
             WIREs website.},
   Doi = {10.1002/wcs.1405},
   Key = {fds321758}
}

@article{fds317720,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Liberal bias and the five-factor model.},
   Journal = {Behavioral and Brain Sciences},
   Volume = {38},
   Pages = {e139},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0140525x14001174},
   Abstract = {Duarte et al. draw attention to the "embedding of liberal
             values and methods" in social psychological research. They
             note how these biases are often invisible to the researchers
             themselves. The authors themselves fall prey to these
             "invisible biases" by utilizing the five-factor model of
             personality and the trait of openness to experience as one
             possible explanation for the under-representation of
             political conservatives in social psychology. I show that
             the manner in which the trait of openness to experience is
             conceptualized and measured is a particularly blatant
             example of the very liberal bias the authors
             decry.},
   Doi = {10.1017/s0140525x14001174},
   Key = {fds317720}
}

@article{fds269914,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Conservatives, liberals, and "the negative".},
   Journal = {Behavioral and Brain Sciences},
   Volume = {37},
   Number = {3},
   Pages = {310-311},
   Year = {2014},
   Month = {June},
   ISSN = {0140-525X},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0140525x13002549},
   Abstract = {The authors connect conservatism with aversion to negativity
             via the tendentious use of the language of threats to
             characterize conservatism, but not liberalism. Their
             reliance upon an objective conception of the negative
             ignores the fact that much of the disagreement between
             liberals and conservatives is over whether or not one and
             the same state of affairs is negative or
             positive.},
   Doi = {10.1017/s0140525x13002549},
   Key = {fds269914}
}

@article{fds317721,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Behavioural Genetics in the Postgenomics
             Era},
   Publisher = {JOHN WILEY & SONS LTD},
   Year = {2014},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9780470015902.a0025250},
   Abstract = {There is growing evidence that the complexity of higher
             organisms does not correlate with the ‘complexity’ of
             the genome (the human genome contains fewer protein coding
             genes than corn, and many genes are preserved across
             species). Rather, complexity is associated with the
             complexity of the pathways and processes whereby the cell
             utilises the deoxyribonucleic acid molecule, and much else,
             in the process of phenotype formation. These pro- cesses
             include the activity of the epigenome, noncoding ribonucleic
             acids, alternative splicing and post-transla- tional
             modifications. Not accidentally, all of these pro- cesses
             appear to be of particular importance for the human brain,
             the most complex organ in nature. Because these processes
             can be highly environmentally reactive, they are a key to
             understanding behavioural plasticity and highlight the
             importance of the developmental process in explaining
             behavioural outcomes.},
   Doi = {10.1002/9780470015902.a0025250},
   Key = {fds317721}
}

@article{fds219098,
   Author = {E. Charney},
   Title = {Can Tasks be Inherently Boring? Commentary on Robert
             Kurzban, Angela Duckworth, Joseph W. Kable, and Justus
             Myers, “An Opportunity Cost Model of Subjective Effort and
             Task Performance"},
   Journal = {Behavioral and Brain Sciences},
   Volume = {36},
   Number = {6},
   Pages = {684},
   Year = {2013},
   Month = {December},
   Abstract = {Kurzban et al. argue that the experiences of “effort,”
             “boredom,” and “fatigue” are indications that the
             costs of a task outweigh its benefits. Reducing the costs of
             tasks to “opportunity costs” has the effect of rendering
             tasks costless and of denying that they can be inherently
             boring or tedious, something that “vigilance tasks” were
             intentionally designed to be.},
   Key = {fds219098}
}

@article{fds269915,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Can tasks be inherently boring?},
   Journal = {Behavioral and Brain Sciences},
   Volume = {36},
   Number = {6},
   Pages = {684},
   Year = {2013},
   Month = {December},
   url = {http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/24304781},
   Abstract = {Kurzban et al. argue that the experiences of "effort,"
             "boredom," and "fatigue" are indications that the costs of a
             task outweigh its benefits. Reducing the costs of tasks to
             "opportunity costs" has the effect of rendering tasks
             costless and of denying that they can be inherently boring
             or tedious, something that "vigilance tasks" were
             intentionally designed to be.},
   Doi = {10.1017/s0140525x13000964},
   Key = {fds269915}
}

@article{fds217523,
   Author = {E. Charney},
   Title = {Politics and Biology},
   Journal = {Perspectives on Politics},
   Volume = {11},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {588-61},
   Year = {2013},
   Month = {June},
   url = {https://drive.google.com/file/d/0BxhbtIT-dOvENDNJSkVSLWR1Z2s/edit?usp=sharing},
   Doi = {10.1017/S1537592713000893},
   Key = {fds217523}
}

@article{fds317722,
   Author = {Alford, CF},
   Title = {Politics and Biology},
   Journal = {Perspectives on Politics},
   Volume = {11},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {549-551},
   Publisher = {Cambridge University Press (CUP)},
   Year = {2013},
   Month = {June},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1537592713000182},
   Abstract = {<jats:p><jats:bold>Man Is by Nature a Political Animal:
             Evolution, Biology, and Politics.</jats:bold> Edited by
             Peter K. Hatemi and Rose McDermott. Chicago: The University
             of Chicago Press, 2011. 352p. $80.00 cloth, $27.50
             paper.</jats:p><jats:p>Peter K. Hatemi and Rose McDermott's
             <jats:italic>Man Is by Nature a Political
             Animal</jats:italic> brings together some of the most
             important social scientists working at the intersection of
             political science, psychology, biology, and cognitive
             neuroscience. Given recent advances in cognitive
             neuroscience and given the proliferation of work in
             political science that draws on these advances, we have
             decided to invite a range of political scientists to comment
             on the promise and the limits of this line of inquiry. What
             can scientific developments in psychology, biology, and
             neuroscience tell us about “human nature”? Can these
             discourses reckon with the variation in time and space that
             has traditionally been at the heart of political science,
             perhaps even going back to the classic text from which
             Hatemi and McDermott derive their title, Aristotle's
             <jats:italic>Politics</jats:italic>?—Jeffrey C. Isaac,
             Editor</jats:p>},
   Doi = {10.1017/s1537592713000182},
   Key = {fds317722}
}

@article{fds269917,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Cytoplasmic inheritance redux.},
   Journal = {Advances in Child Development and Behavior},
   Volume = {44},
   Pages = {225-255},
   Year = {2013},
   Month = {January},
   ISSN = {0065-2407},
   url = {https://drive.google.com/file/d/0BxhbtIT-dOvEZXR1Y2lUckJYWWc/edit?usp=sharing},
   Keywords = {Cytoplasmic Inheritance • Oocyte • Maternal Effect
             Genes • Epigenetics • Histone Modification •
             DNA Methylation • Imprinting • Noncoding RNAs
             • X-chromosome Inactivation • Cytoplasmic
             Organelles • Mitochondria • Nucleoli •
             Assisted Reproductive Technology • IVF and Epigenetics
             • The Oviductal Environment},
   Abstract = {Since the early twentieth century, inheritance was seen as
             the inheritance of genes. Concurrent with the acceptance of
             the genetic theory of inheritance was the rejection of the
             idea that the cytoplasm of the oocyte could also play a role
             in inheritance and a corresponding devaluation of embryology
             as a discipline critical for understanding human
             development. Development, and variation in development, came
             to be viewed solely as matters of genetic inheritance and
             genetic variation. We now know that inheritance is a matter
             of both genetic and cytoplasmic inheritance. A growing
             awareness of the centrality of the cytoplasm in explaining
             both human development and phenotypic variation has been
             promoted by two contemporaneous developments: the continuing
             elaboration of the molecular mechanisms of epigenetics and
             the global rise of artificial reproductive technologies. I
             review recent developments in the ongoing elaboration of the
             role of the cytoplasm in human inheritance and
             development.},
   Doi = {10.1016/b978-0-12-397947-6.00008-8},
   Key = {fds269917}
}

@article{fds269918,
   Author = {Charney, E and English, W},
   Title = {Genopolitics and the science of genetics},
   Journal = {American Political Science Review},
   Volume = {107},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {382-395},
   Publisher = {Cambridge University Press (CUP)},
   Year = {2013},
   Month = {January},
   ISSN = {0003-0554},
   url = {https://drive.google.com/file/d/0BxhbtIT-dOvEZm9SY2tvMlZhaW8/edit?usp=sharing},
   Abstract = {In an earlier article we challenged the findings of Fowler
             and Dawes (FD) that two genes predict voter turnout as part
             of a more general critique of genopolitics. FD now
             acknowledge that their finding of a significant direct
             association between MAOA and voting was incorrect, but claim
             to have replicated their finding of an indirect association
             between 5HTT, self-reported church attendance, and
             self-reported voting. We show that this finding is likely
             driven by population stratification and omitted variable
             bias. We then explain why, from the standpoints of genetics,
             neuroscience, and evolutionary biology, genopolitics is a
             fundamentally misguided undertaking; we also respond to FD's
             charge that some of our previous statements concerning
             genetics are highly misleading, extremely disingenuous, and
             even incorrect. We show that their criticisms demonstrate a
             lack of awareness of some basic principles in genetics and
             of discoveries in molecular genetics over the past 50 years.
             Copyright © 2013 American Political Science
             Association.},
   Doi = {10.1017/S0003055413000099},
   Key = {fds269918}
}

@article{fds219099,
   Author = {E. Charney},
   Title = {Conservatives, liberals, and "the negative": Commentary on
             John R. Hibbing, Kevin B. Smith, and John R. Alford,
             "Differences in Negativity Bias Underlie Variations in
             Political Ideology"},
   Journal = {Behavioral and Brain Sciences},
   Year = {2013},
   Key = {fds219099}
}

@article{fds219100,
   Author = {E. Charney},
   Title = {Behavioural genetics in the postgenomic era},
   Journal = {eLS, John Wiley & Sons},
   Year = {2013},
   Abstract = {There is growing evidence that the complexity of higher
             organisms does not correlate with the “complexity” of
             the genome (the human genome contains fewer protein coding
             genes than corn, and many genes are preserved across
             species). Rather, complexity is associated with the
             complexity of the pathways and processes whereby the cell
             utilizes the DNA molecule, and much else, in the process of
             phenotype formation. These processes include the activity of
             the epigenome, non-coding RNAs, alternative splicing, and
             post-translational modifications. Not accidentally, all of
             these processes appear to be of particular importance for
             the human brain, the most complex organ in nature. Because
             these processes can be highly environmentally reactive, they
             are a key to understanding behavioural plasticity and
             highlight the importance of the developmental process in
             explaining behavioural outcomes.},
   Key = {fds219100}
}

@article{fds269924,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Behavior Genetics and Post Genomics},
   Journal = {Behavioral and Brain Sciences},
   Volume = {35},
   Number = {6},
   Pages = {1-80},
   Year = {2012},
   Month = {December},
   url = {https://docs.google.com/open?id=0BxhbtIT-dOvEVFBBTEs5dEZMc2c},
   Keywords = {genetics, behavior genetics, heritability, epigenetics, twin
             studies, gene association studies, developmental biology,
             phenotypic plasticity, evolutionary developmental biology,
             evo-devo, maternal effects, stochasticity},
   Abstract = {The science of genetics is undergoing a paradigm shift.
             Recent discoveries, including the activity of
             retrotransposons, the extent of copy number variations,
             somatic and chromosomal mosaicism, and the nature of the
             epigenome as a regulator of DNA expressivity, are
             challenging a series of dogmas concerning the nature of the
             genome and the relationship between genotype and phenotype.
             DNA, once held to be the unchanging template of heredity,
             now appears subject to a good deal of environmental change;
             considered to be identical in all cells and tissues of the
             body, there is growing evidence that somatic mosaicism is
             the normal human condition; and treated as the sole
             biological agent of heritability, we now know that the
             epigenome, which regulates gene expressivity, can be
             inherited via the germline. These developments are
             particularly significant for behavior genetics for at least
             three reasons: First, these phenomena appear to be
             particularly prevalent in the human brain, and likely are
             involved in much of human behavior; second, they have
             important implications for the validity of heritability and
             gene association studies, the methodologies that largely
             define the discipline of behavior genetics; and third, they
             appear to play a critical role in development during the
             perinatal period, and in enabling phenotypic plasticity in
             offspring in particular. I examine one of the central claims
             to emerge from the use of heritability studies in the
             behavioral sciences, the principle of “minimal shared
             maternal effects,” in light of the growing awareness that
             the maternal perinatal environment is a critical venue for
             the exercise of adaptive phenotypic plasticity. This
             consideration has important implications for both
             developmental and evolutionary biology},
   Doi = {10.1017/S0140525X11002226},
   Key = {fds269924}
}

@article{fds269923,
   Author = {Chamey, E and English, W},
   Title = {The voting gene.},
   Journal = {Scientific American},
   Volume = {307},
   Number = {5},
   Pages = {14},
   Year = {2012},
   Month = {November},
   ISSN = {0036-8733},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/scientificamerican1112-14},
   Doi = {10.1038/scientificamerican1112-14},
   Key = {fds269923}
}

@article{fds269921,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Author’s response: Humans, fruit flies, and
             automatons.},
   Journal = {Behavioral and Brain Sciences},
   Volume = {35},
   Number = {5},
   Pages = {381-410},
   Publisher = {Cambridge University Press (CUP)},
   Year = {2012},
   Month = {October},
   ISSN = {0140-525X},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X12001501},
   Abstract = {My response is divided into four sections: (1) is devoted to
             a potpourri of commentaries that are essentially in
             agreement with the substance of my target article (with one
             exception); in (2) I address, in response to one of the
             commentaries, several issues relating to the use of
             candidate gene association studies in behavior genetics (in
             particular those proposing a specific G × E interaction);
             in (3) I provide a detailed response to several defenses of
             the twin study methodology; and in (4) I conclude with
             several reflections on that methodology and the conception
             of human nature it has fostered.},
   Doi = {10.1017/S0140525X12001501},
   Key = {fds269921}
}

@article{fds269922,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Behavior genetics and postgenomics.},
   Journal = {Behavioral and Brain Sciences},
   Volume = {35},
   Number = {5},
   Pages = {331-358},
   Year = {2012},
   Month = {October},
   url = {http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/23095378},
   Abstract = {The science of genetics is undergoing a paradigm shift.
             Recent discoveries, including the activity of
             retrotransposons, the extent of copy number variations,
             somatic and chromosomal mosaicism, and the nature of the
             epigenome as a regulator of DNA expressivity, are
             challenging a series of dogmas concerning the nature of the
             genome and the relationship between genotype and phenotype.
             According to three widely held dogmas, DNA is the unchanging
             template of heredity, is identical in all the cells and
             tissues of the body, and is the sole agent of inheritance.
             Rather than being an unchanging template, DNA appears
             subject to a good deal of environmentally induced change.
             Instead of identical DNA in all the cells of the body,
             somatic mosaicism appears to be the normal human condition.
             And DNA can no longer be considered the sole agent of
             inheritance. We now know that the epigenome, which regulates
             gene expressivity, can be inherited via the germline. These
             developments are particularly significant for behavior
             genetics for at least three reasons: First, epigenetic
             regulation, DNA variability, and somatic mosaicism appear to
             be particularly prevalent in the human brain and probably
             are involved in much of human behavior; second, they have
             important implications for the validity of heritability and
             gene association studies, the methodologies that largely
             define the discipline of behavior genetics; and third, they
             appear to play a critical role in development during the
             perinatal period and, in particular, in enabling phenotypic
             plasticity in offspring. I examine one of the central claims
             to emerge from the use of heritability studies in the
             behavioral sciences, the principle of minimal shared
             maternal effects, in light of the growing awareness that the
             maternal perinatal environment is a critical venue for the
             exercise of adaptive phenotypic plasticity. This
             consideration has important implications for both
             developmental and evolutionary biology.},
   Doi = {10.1017/s0140525x11002226},
   Key = {fds269922}
}

@article{fds269925,
   Author = {Charney, E and English, W},
   Title = {Candidate genes and political behavior},
   Journal = {American Political Science Review},
   Volume = {106},
   Number = {1},
   Pages = {1-34},
   Publisher = {Cambridge University Press (CUP)},
   Year = {2012},
   Month = {February},
   ISSN = {0003-0554},
   url = {https://docs.google.com/open?id=0BxhbtIT-dOvESm51d1BlNnRTTHFQcFNaWlNMRUtRdw},
   Abstract = {Political scientists are making increasing use of the
             methodologies of behavior genetics in an attempt to uncover
             whether or not political behavior is heritable, as well as
             the specific genotypes that might act as predisposing
             factors for-or predictors of-political henotypes. Noteworthy
             among the latter are a series of candidate gene association
             studies in which researchers claim to have discovered one or
             two common genetic variants that predict such behaviors as
             voting and political orientation. We critically examine the
             candidate gene association study methodology by considering,
             as a representative example, the recent study by Fowler and
             Dawes according to which two genes predict voter turnout. In
             addition to demonstrating, on the basis of the data set
             employed by Fowler and Dawes, that two genes do not predict
             voter turnout, we consider a number of difficulties, both
             methodological and genetic, that beset the use of gene
             association studies, both candidate and genome-wide, in the
             social and behavioral sciences. © 2012 American Political
             Science Association.},
   Doi = {10.1017/S0003055411000554},
   Key = {fds269925}
}

@article{fds269916,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Political science and behavior genetics: Rethinking
             foundational assumptions},
   Journal = {Research in Biopolitics},
   Volume = {9},
   Pages = {115-138},
   Booktitle = {Biology and Politics: The Cutting Edge},
   Publisher = {Emerald Group Publishing Limited},
   Year = {2011},
   Month = {December},
   ISSN = {2042-9940},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1108/S2042-9940(2011)0000009007},
   Doi = {10.1108/S2042-9940(2011)0000009007},
   Key = {fds269916}
}

@article{fds269926,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Physiology may not be (political) destiny},
   Journal = {Psycrit},
   Year = {2009},
   Month = {February},
   url = {http://tinyurl.com/politics-reflexes},
   Abstract = {Oxley et al. (2008) translate an eyeblink and a slight
             sweat, provoked by different kinds of pictures, into a
             political position. Science magazine apparently raised no
             objections. Charney points out that both eye blinks and GSR
             changes can be interpreted in very many ways. Oxley et
             al.’s grand conclusions leave their modest data well
             behind.},
   Key = {fds269926}
}

@article{fds269927,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Politics, genetics, and "greedy reductionism"},
   Journal = {Perspectives on Politics},
   Volume = {6},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {337-343},
   Publisher = {Cambridge University Press (CUP)},
   Year = {2008},
   Month = {June},
   ISSN = {1537-5927},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S1537592708080651},
   Doi = {10.1017/S1537592708080651},
   Key = {fds269927}
}

@article{fds269928,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Genes and ideologies},
   Journal = {Perspectives on Politics},
   Volume = {6},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {299-319},
   Publisher = {Cambridge University Press (CUP)},
   Year = {2008},
   Month = {June},
   ISSN = {1537-5927},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S1537592708080626},
   Abstract = {There is a trend among behavioral scientists to view ever
             more complex attitudes or systems of belief as in some sense
             genetically determined (or "heritable"). Consistent with
             this trend is the recent article of Alford, Funk, and
             Hibbing titled "Are Political Orientations Genetically
             Transmitted?" in which the authors claim to have
             demonstrated that when it comes to the transmission of
             political ideologies, genes count for more than environment.
             Their article has received an enormous amount of attention
             among political scientists and in the popular press. I
             critically evaluate the research technique on the basis of
             which the authors' support their claims and argue that it
             suffers from significant methodological flaws. Such flaws
             notwithstanding, I demonstrate that the authors' data do not
             clearly support their conclusions. I then question the
             cogency, from an historical and theoretical perspective, of
             proposing the existence of "liberal" and "conservative"
             "phenotypes" and "genotypes." My argument has implications
             beyond the findings of Alford, Funk, and Hibbing, and
             applies to all studies that claim to have demonstrated the
             heritability of complex and politically relevant attitudes.
             © 2008 Copyright American Political Science
             Association.},
   Doi = {10.1017/S1537592708080626},
   Key = {fds269928}
}

@article{fds317723,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Why Deliberative Democracy?by Amy Gutmann and Dennis
             Thompson},
   Journal = {Political Science Quarterly},
   Volume = {120},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {310-311},
   Publisher = {WILEY},
   Year = {2005},
   Month = {June},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/j.1538-165x.2005.tb01361.x},
   Doi = {10.1002/j.1538-165x.2005.tb01361.x},
   Key = {fds317723}
}

@article{fds269929,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Identity and liberal nationalism},
   Journal = {American Political Science Review},
   Volume = {97},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {295-310},
   Publisher = {Cambridge University Press (CUP)},
   Year = {2003},
   Month = {May},
   ISSN = {0003-0554},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0003055403000686},
   Abstract = {A number of liberal defenders of nationalism argue that
             cultural-national membership is a vital component of
             individual identity. Notable among these liberal "identity
             nationalists" is Will Kymlicka, who defends minority
             national and cultural rights on the basis of the importance
             of such membership for persons' sense of identity.
             Kymlicka's conception of the liberal autonomous self,
             however, is radically at odds with his views concerning the
             importance of cultural-national membership. It also
             privileges national identity in such a way as to lend
             support to an extreme and illiberal form of nationalism, one
             that bases the priority of national obligations on the
             priority of national identity. By prioritizing national
             identity as Kymlicka does, other nonnational sites of
             identity formation, such as religious communities, may
             receive inadequate protection in a pluralistic
             nation-state.},
   Doi = {10.1017/S0003055403000686},
   Key = {fds269929}
}

@article{fds269919,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Cultural interpretation and universal human rights: A
             response to Daniel A. Bell},
   Journal = {Political Theory},
   Volume = {27},
   Number = {6},
   Pages = {840-848},
   Publisher = {SAGE Publications},
   Year = {1999},
   Month = {January},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0090591799027006006},
   Doi = {10.1177/0090591799027006006},
   Key = {fds269919}
}

@article{fds269920,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Political liberalism, deliberative democracy, and the public
             sphere},
   Journal = {American Political Science Review},
   Volume = {92},
   Number = {1},
   Pages = {97-110},
   Year = {1998},
   ISSN = {0003-0554},
   url = {http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2585931},
   Abstract = {Theorists of democracy emphasize the importance of a public
             sphere, distinct from the apparatus of the state, where
             citizens can freely associate, deliberate, and engage in
             collective will formation. Discourse ethicists and
             deliberative democrats locate the public sphere within civil
             society and the manifold associations that comprise it. For
             Seyla Benhabib, the public sphere is constituted by the
             anonymous "public conversation" of civil society. By
             contrast, John Rawls has a much more limited conception of
             the public sphere. For Rawls, public reason, which
             establishes norms for democratic discourse, applies to a
             limited domain. I defend Rawls's view against the charge
             that it depends upon an untenable distinction between the
             public and nonpublic spheres. I argue that Rawls's more
             limited "liberal" conception better guarantees the
             heterogeneity of associational life in civil society. I then
             argue that Rawls violates his own principles by partially
             collapsing the public-nonpublic distinction with potentially
             illiberal consequences.},
   Doi = {10.2307/2585931},
   Key = {fds269920}
}


%% Chapters in Books   
@misc{fds219103,
   Author = {E. Charney},
   Title = {Genetics and the Life Course},
   Booktitle = {Emerging Trends in the Social and Behavioral
             Sciences},
   Year = {2013},
   Abstract = {A life course perspective is committed to the proposition
             that from conception to death, all human outcomes are the
             result of a continual interaction between the individual and
             all of the environments that he or she inhabits at any given
             point in time. Early development is a critical period, a
             window of time during the life course when a given exposure
             can have a critical or permanent influence on later
             outcomes. But the impact of exposures upon outcomes does not
             end at any specific point in time, inasmuch as life is a
             continuing interactive and adaptive process. We now know
             that what applies to human beings, also applies to their
             genomes. The “outcome” of any gene at any given point in
             time (whether or not it is used to transcribe a particular
             protein, what form of that protein, and how much) is a
             product of the interaction between the gene and the multiple
             environments of which it is a part, which includes the
             epigenome, the cell, the biological human, and the assorted
             environments he or she occupies (e.g., geographical,
             socio-economic, ethnic, etc.). Early life experiences can
             permanently “reprogram” the epigenome and gene
             transcription with life-long behavioral consequences. At the
             same time, the epigenome as well as the genome continue to
             be environmentally responsive throughout the life
             course.},
   Key = {fds219103}
}

@misc{fds217522,
   Author = {E. Charney},
   Title = {Gene Association Studies},
   Booktitle = {Biotechnology in Our Lives},
   Publisher = {Skyhorse},
   Address = {New York, NY},
   Editor = {Sheldon Krimsky and Jeremy Gruber},
   Year = {2013},
   Key = {fds217522}
}

@misc{fds52962,
   Author = {E. Charney},
   Title = {Political Ethics},
   Booktitle = {International Encyclopedia of Political Science},
   Publisher = {CQ Press},
   Editor = {George T. Kurian},
   Year = {2010},
   Month = {January},
   Key = {fds52962}
}

@misc{fds52961,
   Author = {E. Charney},
   Title = {Political Correctness; Faith-Based Initiatives; Flag
             Desecration},
   Booktitle = {Encyclopedia of the Culture Wars},
   Publisher = {M.E. Sharpe},
   Editor = {Roger Chapman},
   Year = {2009},
   Month = {December},
   Key = {fds52961}
}


%% Book Reviews   
@article{fds32290,
   Author = {E. Charney},
   Title = {Why Deliberative Democracy? by Amy Gutmann and Dennis
             Thompson},
   Journal = {Political Science Quarterly},
   Year = {2005},
   Key = {fds32290}
}

@article{fds32291,
   Author = {E. Charney},
   Title = {Restoring the Lost Constitution by Randy E.
             Barnett},
   Journal = {Perspectives on Politics},
   Volume = {2},
   Number = {3},
   Year = {2004},
   Month = {September},
   Key = {fds32291}
}

@article{fds32292,
   Author = {E. Charney},
   Title = {Libertarianism Without Inequality by Michael
             Otsuka},
   Journal = {Perspectives on Politics},
   Volume = {2},
   Number = {3},
   Year = {2004},
   Month = {September},
   Key = {fds32292}
}

@article{fds14343,
   Author = {E. Charney},
   Title = {Liberal Purposes by William Galston},
   Journal = {Perspectives on Politics},
   Volume = {1},
   Number = {2},
   Pages = {384-85},
   Year = {2003},
   Month = {June},
   Key = {fds14343}
}


%% Op-eds   
@misc{fds219097,
   Author = {E. Charney},
   Title = {Still Chasing Ghosts: A New Genetic Methodology Will Not
             Find the “Missing Heritability”},
   Journal = {Independent Science News},
   Year = {2013},
   Month = {September},
   url = {http://www.independentsciencenews.org/health/still-chasing-ghosts-a-new-genetic-methodology-will-not-find-the-missing-heritability/},
   Key = {fds219097}
}

@misc{fds153319,
   Author = {E. Charney},
   Title = {“Debunking the Threat-Sweat Thinking Theory”},
   Journal = {Raleigh News and Observer},
   Year = {2008},
   Month = {September},
   Key = {fds153319}
}


%% Book Chapter   
@misc{fds317719,
   Author = {Charney, E},
   Title = {Genetics and the Life Course},
   Booktitle = {Emerging Trends in the Social and Behavioral
             Sciences},
   Publisher = {John Wiley & Sons},
   Year = {2015},
   Month = {January},
   Abstract = {A life-course perspective is committed to the proposition
             that from conception to death, all human outcomes are the
             result of a continual interaction between the indi- vidual
             and all of the environments that he or she inhabits at any
             given point in time. Early development is a critical period,
             a window of time during the life course when a given
             exposure can have a critical or permanent in uence on later
             outcomes. But the impact of exposures upon outcomes does not
             end at any speci c point in time, inasmuch as life is a
             continuing interactive and adaptive process. We now know
             that what applies to human beings also applies to their
             genomes. The “outcome” of any gene at any given point in
             time (whether or not it is used to transcribe a particular
             protein, what form of that protein, and how much) is a
             product of the interaction between the gene and the multiple
             environments of which it is a part, which include the
             epigenome, the cell, the biological human, and the assorted
             environments he or she occupies (e.g., geographical,
             socioeconomic, ethnic, etc.). Early life experiences can
             permanently “reprogram” the epigenome and gene
             transcription with life-long behavioral consequences. At the
             same time, the epigenome as well as the genome continue to
             be environmentally responsive throughout the life
             course.},
   Key = {fds317719}
}

Evan Charney